•  210
    Materialism and action
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 35 (4): 501-511. 1975.
  •  146
    Direct realism: Proximate causation and the missing object (review)
    Acta Analytica 20 (36): 3-6. 2005.
    Direct Realists believe that perception involves direct awareness of an object not dependent for its existence on the perceiver. Howard Robinson rejects this doctrine in favour of a Sense-Datum theory of perception. His argument against Direct Realism invokes the principle ‘same proximate cause, same immediate effect’. Since there are cases in which direct awareness has the same proximate cerebral cause as awareness of a sense datum, the Direct Realist is, he thinks, obliged to deny this causal …Read more
  •  125
    The Multiplication of Utility: N. M. L. Nathan
    Utilitas 6 (2): 217-218. 1994.
    Some people have supposed that utility is good in itself, non-in-strumentally good, as distinct from good because conducive to other good things. And in modern versions of this view, utility often means want-satisfaction, as distinct from pleasure or happiness. For your want that p to be satisfied, is it necessary that you know or believe that p, or sufficient merely that p is true? However that question is answered, there are problems with the view that want-satisfaction is a non-instrumental g…Read more
  •  93
    Book review. The nature of perception John Foster (review)
    Mind 110 (438): 455-460. 2001.
  •  91
    Naturalism and self-defeat: Plantinga's version
    Religious Studies 33 (2): 135-142. 1997.
    In "Warrant and Proper Function" Plantinga argues that atheistic Naturalism is self-defeating. What is the probability that our cognitive faculties are reliable, given this Naturalism and an evolutionary explanation of their origins? Plantinga argues that if the Naturalist is modest enough to believe that it is irrational to have any belief as to the value of this probability, then he is irrational even to believe his own Naturalism. I suggest that Plantinga's argument has a false premise, and t…Read more
  •  87
    Substance Dualism Fortified
    Philosophy 86 (2): 201-211. 2011.
    You have a body, but you are a soul or self. Without your body, you could still exist. Your body could be and perhaps is outlasted by the immaterial substance which is your soul or self. Thus the substance dualist. Most substance dualists are Cartesians. The self, they suppose, is essentially conscious: it cannot exist unless it thinks or wills or has experiences. In this paper I sketch out a different form of substance dualism. I suggest that it is not consciousness but another immaterial featu…Read more
  •  86
    Jewish monotheism and the Christian God
    Religious Studies 42 (1): 75-85. 2006.
    Some Christians combine a doctrine about Christ which implies that there is more than one divine self with the doctrine that God revealed to the Jews a monotheism according to which there is just one divine self. I suggest that it is less costly for such Christians to achieve consistency by abandoning the second of these doctrines than to achieve it by abandoning the first.
  •  79
    `Egalitarianism'
    Mind 92 (367): 413-416. 1983.
  •  72
    Exclusion and sufficient reason
    Philosophy 85 (3): 391-397. 2010.
    I argue for two principles by combining which we can construct a sound cosmological argument. The first is that for any true proposition p's if 'there is an explanation for p's truth' is consistent then there is an explanation for p's truth. The second is a modified version of the principle that for any class, if there is an explanation for the non-emptiness ofthat class, then there is at least one non-member ofthat class which causes it not to be empty
  •  71
    Murder and the death of Christ
    Think 9 (26): 103-107. 2010.
    Some people believe that God made it a condition for His forgiveness even of repentant sinners that Jesus died a sacrificial death at human hands. Often, in the New Testament, this doctrine of Objective Atonement seems to be implied, as when Jesus spoke of his blood as ‘shed for many for the remission of sins’ , or when St Paul said that ‘Christ died for our sins according to the scriptures’ . And for many centuries the doctrine was indeed accepted by most if not all Christian theologians. It se…Read more
  •  67
    Admiration: A New Obstacle
    Philosophy 72 (281). 1997.
  •  66
    Mctaggart's immaterialism
    Philosophical Quarterly 41 (165): 442-456. 1991.
  •  56
    On the Justification of Democracy
    The Monist 55 (1): 89-120. 1971.
    1. The ideal of spatio-temporally unrestricted generalisation, which marks all post-mythological thinking about nature, marks no more than the continuity of totemism in political casuistry. No unrestricted principle of Socialism or Conservatism or Liberal Democracy is defensible unless it is accorded a moral ultimacy which almost no one fully conscious of what he was about would actually want to accord it. If this bare platitude is to be fully assimilated, it needs both concrete exemplification …Read more
  •  49
    Compatibilism and natural necessity
    Mind 84 (April): 277-280. 1975.
  •  45
    Self and will
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (1). 1997.
    When do two mental items belong to the same life? We could be content with the answer -just when they have certain volitional qualities in common. An affinity is noted between that theory and Berkeley's early doctrine of the self. Some rivals of the volitional theory invoke a spiritual or physical owner of mental items. They run a risk either of empty formality or of causal superstition. Other rivals postulate a non-transitive and symmetrical relation in the set of mental items. They must allow …Read more
  •  42
    Exclusion and Sufficient Reason
    Philosophy 85 (3): 391-397. 2010.
    I argue for two principles by combining which we can construct a sound cosmological argument. The first is that for any true proposition p's if ‘there is an explanation for p's truth’ is consistent then there is an explanation for p's truth. The second is a modified version of the principle that for any class, if there is an explanation for the non-emptiness of that class, then there is at least one non-member of that class which causes it not to be empty.
  •  41
    Necessity, Inconceivability and the "A Priori"
    with J. J. Valberg
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 56 (1). 1982.
  •  38
    Evidence and Assurance
    Cambridge University Press. 1980.
    A systematic study of rational or justified belief, which throws fresh light on current debates about foundations and coherence theories of knowledge, the validation of induction and moral scepticism. Dr Nathan focuses attention on the largely unsatisfiable desires for active and self-conscious assurance of truth liable to be engendered by philosophical reflection about total belief-systems and the sources of knowledge. He extracts a kernel of truth from the doctrine that a regress of justificat…Read more
  •  37
    VI*—Scepticism and the Regress of Justification
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 75 (1): 77-88. 1975.
    N. M. L. Nathan; VI*—Scepticism and the Regress of Justification, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 75, Issue 1, 1 June 1975, Pages 77–88, https:/
  •  34
    A new incompatibilism
    Mind 93 (369): 39-55. 1984.
  •  33
    A difficulty about justice
    Mind 80 (318): 227-237. 1971.
  •  32
    On the non-causal explanation of human action
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 6 (3): 241-243. 1976.
  •  31
    Vicious regression and the value of belief
    Philosophia 28 (1-4): 369-372. 2001.
  •  30
    Projectivist utilitarianism
    Erkenntnis 20 (2). 1983.