CV
Hartford, Connecticut, United States of America
Areas of Interest
History of Western Philosophy
  •  175
    CONTRASTING PREJUDICES TRUTH AND FALSEHOOD How can one say something false? How can one even think such a thing? Since, for example, all men are mortal, ...
  •  89
    The principle of harmony
    Analysis 49 (1): 21-22. 1989.
  •  86
    Critical notice of Richard Gaskin's The Unity of the Proposition
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 88 (1). 2010.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  85
    Imagine a child′s toy arrow, sticking by its rubber sucker to a mirror′s reflective surface. We can call the direction in which such an arrow would point the finwards direction ; and we can call the opposite direction boutwards . When we look at things in a mirror, their images are apparently just as far finwards of the mirror as the things themselves are boutwards of it. For example, if we look at the tail of our arrow and cast our glance finwards, we see first the tail, then the head, then the…Read more
  •  82
    Ethics in Plato's Republic
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20 19-32. 1986.
    Why should I be just? What have I to gain if I am decent, honest, moral, upright, fair and truthful? Other people benefit if I am just, but do I? And doesn't it seem clear that sometimes the benefit that other people receive from my being just is a benefit received at my expense? Perhaps then I have no adequate reason to be just. Perhaps if I have any sense I will not bother.
  •  81
    Being, Identity and Truth
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (174): 117. 1994.
    Philosophers have met with many problems in discussing the interconnected concepts being, identity, and truth, and have advanced many theories to deal with them. Professor Williams argues that most of these problems and theories result from an inadequate appreciation of the ways in which the words `be', `same', and `true' work. By means of linguistic analysis he shows that being and truth are not properties, and identity is not a relation. He is thus able to demystify a number of metaphysical is…Read more
  •  79
  •  73
    Plato: Protagoras (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2008.
    The Protagoras is one of Plato's most entertaining dialogues. It represents Socrates at a gathering of the most celebrated and highest-earning intellectuals of the day, among them the sophist Protagoras. In flamboyant displays of both rhetoric and dialectic, Socrates and Protagoras try to out-argue one another. Their arguments range widely, from political theory to literary criticism, from education to the nature of cowardice; but in view throughout this literary and philosophical masterpiece ar…Read more
  •  72
    Plato's Theory of Stuffs
    Philosophy 58 (225). 1983.
    The theory of forms makes a very poor theory of universals. It-or at least the "phaedo's" version of it-makes excellent sense as a theory of the elemental stuffs from which everything is made. This is shown by a detailed examination of all that this "phaedo" has to say about forms
  •  69
    Names, verbs and sentences
    Philosophy 73 (4): 619-623. 1998.
    Metaphysicians often declare that there are large ontological differences (properties versus individuals, universals versus particulars) correlated with the linguistic distinction between names and verbs. Gaskin argues against all such declarations on the grounds that we may quantify with equal ease over the referents of both types of expression. However, his argument must be wrong, given the massive differences between first- and second-order qualification. Its only grain of truth is that these…Read more
  •  68
    Dialetheism and trivialization
    Mind 98 (390): 259-263. 1989.
  •  59
    Names, verbs and quantification again
    Philosophy 74 (3): 439-440. 1999.
    There are enormous differences between quantifying name-variables only, quantifying verb-variables only, and quantifying both. These differences are found only in the logic of polyadic predication; and this presumably is why Richard Gaskin thinks that they distinguish names from transitive verbs only, and not from verbs generally. But that thought is mistaken: these differences also distinguish names from intransitive verbs. They thus vindicate the common idea that on the difference between name…Read more
  •  57
    Pure second-order logic
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 33 (2): 220-224. 1992.
  •  54
    V*—Chess and Life: The Structure of a Moral Code
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 82 (1): 59-68. 1982.
    Nicholas Denyer; V*—Chess and Life: The Structure of a Moral Code, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 82, Issue 1, 1 June 1982, Pages 59–68, https
  •  51
    The Master Argument of Diodorus Chronus: A Near Miss
    History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 2 (1): 239-252. 1999.
    Diodorus' Master Argument was intended to show that whatever is possible either is or will be true. The intended conclusion does not follow from the extant premisses of the Master Argument. The Near Miss argues however, from those premisses alone, that nothing can be more than momentarily an exception to the Master Argument's intended conclusion. Strong arguments support even the most contentious of those premisses . We therefore cannot easily ignore the Near Miss. Moreover, there are various su…Read more
  •  38
    Just war
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 46 137-. 2000.
    The innocent are immune. We must never, that is, make the object of any violent attack those who bear no responsibility for doing wrong to others; and only with grave reason and in extreme circumstances should we be prepared to cause them any incidental harm as we press home a violent attack against those who are its legitimate objects. This principle of the immunity of the innocent seems almost self-evidently true. This is not to say that the principle is incapable of further development and ar…Read more
  •  34
    Ethics in Plato's Republic
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 20 19-32. 1986.
    Why should I be just? What have I to gain if I am decent, honest, moral, upright, fair and truthful? Other people benefit if I am just, but do I? And doesn't it seem clear that sometimes the benefit that other people receive from my being just is a benefit received at my expense? Perhaps then I have no adequate reason to be just. Perhaps if I have any sense I will not bother.
  •  29
    Philoponus, Diodorus, and Possibility
    Classical Quarterly 48 (01): 327-. 1998.
    The definition here ascribed to Philo is entirely in line with what we know of Philo from else where: Alex. Aphr. in APr. 184.6–10; Simp, in Cat. 195.33–196.5; Boethius, in de Int. 234.10–15. The same is not true of the definition here ascribed to Diodorus. For Diodorus, we are told elsewhere, defined the possible as that which either is or will be so: Cic. Fat. 13, 17; Plu. de Stoic rep. 1055d-e; Alex. Aphr. in APr. 183.42–184.5; Boethius, in de Int. 234.22–4,412.16–7. Something has therefore g…Read more
  •  21
    The Master Argument of Diodorus Cronus
    History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 2 (1): 239-252. 1999.