•  49
    Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism (edited book)
    with David Copp
    Oxford University Press. 2023.
    Morality seems to play a special role in human life distinct from conventional norms, like those of etiquette, or simple preferences based on subjective tastes. There are various theories of the foundations of morality, some of which treat morality as 'subjective' in an important way. 'Moral realism' is however a family of theories that take morality to have an objective factual basis, such that morality is not 'up to us' and is not 'under our control'. The contributions in this handbook explore…Read more
  •  192
    Function, Fitness, Flourishing
    In Paul Bloomfield & David Copp (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism, Oxford University Press. pp. 264-292. 2023.
  •  108
    The Skills of Justice
    In Ellen Fridland & Pavase Carlotta (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Skills and Expertise, Rutledge. pp. 460-475. 2021.
  •  201
    Humility Is Not A Virtue
    In Mark Alfano, Michael Patrick Lynch & Alessandra Tanesini (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Humility, Routledge. pp. 36-46. 2021.
  •  250
    The Axiology of Pain and Pleasure
    Journal of Value Inquiry 1-24. forthcoming.
    There is little more common in ethics than to think pain is intrinsically bad and pleasure is intrinsically good. A Humean-style error theory of the axiology of pain and pleasure is developed against these commonsense claims. We defend the thesis that the value of pain and pleasure is always contingent and only instrumental. We survey prominent theories of both intrinsic value and pain/pleasure, all of which assume that pain and pleasure are intrinsically valuable. We base our error theory o…Read more
  •  84
    On human rights * by James Griffin (review)
    Analysis 71 (1): 195-197. 2011.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  38
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  16
    Beyond the Basics of Emotions (review)
    Journal of Philosophy of Emotion 3 (1): 24-30. 2021.
    While emotions can play positive, contributory roles in our cognition and our lives, they frequently have the opposite effect. Michael Brady’s otherwise excellent introduction to the topic of emotion is unbalanced because he does not attend to harms emotions cause. The basic problem is that emotions have a normative aspect: they can be justified or unjustified and Brady does not attend to this. An example of this is Brady’s discussion of curiosity as the emotional motivation for knowledge. More …Read more
  •  309
    Naturalistic Moral Realism and Evolutionary Biology
    Philosophies 7 (1): 2. 2021.
    Perhaps the most familiar understanding of “naturalism” derives from Quine, understanding it as a continuity of empirical theories of the world as described through the scientific method. So, it might be surprising that one of the most important naturalistic moral realists, Philippa Foot, rejects standard evolutionary biology in her justly lauded _Natural Goodness_. One of her main reasons for this is the true claim that humans can flourish (eudaimonia) without reproducing, which she claims cann…Read more
  •  631
    Virtues are excellences
    Ratio 35 (1): 49-60. 2021.
    One of the few points of unquestioned agreement in virtue theory is that the virtues are supposed to be excellences. The best way to understand the project of "virtue ethics" is to understand this claim as the idea that the virtues always yield correct moral action and, therefore, that we cannot be “too virtuous”. In other words, the virtues cannot be had in excess or “to a fault”. If we take this seriously, however, it yields the surprising conclusion that many traits which have been traditiona…Read more
  •  171
    Epistemic Temperance
    American Philosophical Quarterly 56 (2): 109-124. 2019.
    The idea of epistemic temperance is introduced and explicated through a discussion of Plato's understanding of it. A variety of psychological and epistemic phenomena are presented which arise due to epistemic intemperance, or the inappropriate influence of conations on cognition. Two cases familiar to philosophers, self-deception and racial prejudice, are discussed as the result of epistemic intemperance though they are not typically seen as having a common cause. Finally, epistemic temperance i…Read more
  •  611
    The Character of the Hypocrite
    Journal of Philosophical Research 43 69-82. 2018.
    A distinction is made between acting hypocritically and the character trait of being a hypocrite. The former is understood as resulting from the employment of a double standard in order to obtain a wrongful advantage, while a particular problem with the latter is that hypocrites do not give trustworthy testimony.
  •  226
    Justice as a Self‐Regarding Virtue
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (1): 46-64. 2010.
  •  163
    Archimedeanism and Why Metaethics Matters
    Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4 283-302. 2009.
  •  593
    Tracking Eudaimonia
    Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 10 (2). 2018.
    A basic challenge to naturalistic moral realism is that, even if moral properties existed, there would be no way to naturalistically represent or track them. Here, the basic structure for a tracking account of moral epistemology is given in empirically respectable terms, based on a eudaimonist conception of morality. The goal is to show how this form of moral realism can be seen as consistent with the details of evolutionary biology as well as being amenable to the most current understanding of …Read more
  •  1651
    Morality is necessary for happiness
    Philosophical Studies 174 (10): 2613-2628. 2017.
    An argument for the eponymous conclusion is given through a series of hypothetical syllogisms, the most basic of which is as follows: morality is necessary for self-respect; self-respect is necessary for happiness; therefore, morality is necessary for happiness. Some of the most obvious objections are entertained and rejected.
  •  16
    Partially Re‐Humanized Ethics: Comments on Butchvarov
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (S1): 184-189. 2003.
  •  19
    Well-Being: Happiness in a Worthwhile Life (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 69 (3): 613-614. 2016.
  •  65
    The Moral Skeptic, by Anita M. Superson (review)
    Mind 120 (479): 914-917. 2011.
  •  13
    Opening questions, following rules
    In Terry Horgan & Mark Timmons (eds.), Metaethics After Moore, Oxford University Press. pp. 169. 2006.
  •  139
    Is There Moral High Ground?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (4): 511-526. 2003.
  •  44
    Undeniably, life is unfair. So, why play fairly in an unfair world? The answer comes from combining the ancient Greek conception of happiness with a modern conception of self-respect. The book is about why it is bad to be bad and good to be good, and what happens in between.
  •  33
    Review: The Evolution of Morality (review)
    Mind 116 (461): 176-180. 2007.
  •  577
    Moral Point of View (2nd ed.)
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Blackwell. 2013.
  •  79
    Dennett's misremenberings
    Philosophia 26 (1-2): 207-218. 1998.
  •  37
    Why it's bad to be bad
    In Morality and Self-Interest, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    The question “Why is it bad to be bad?” might seem either tautologous or poorly formed. It may seem like a tautology because it seems logical to think that badness is necessarily bad and so it must, of course, follow that it is bad to be bad. It might seem to be malformed because it may seem like anyone who asks the question, “Why is it bad to be bad?” must fail to understand the meaning of the words they are using: generally, if something is X, it cannot fail to be X. If so, then it may seem as…Read more
  •  39
    The Normative Web (review)
    Social Theory and Practice 36 (1): 157-164. 2010.