•  1636
    Morality is necessary for happiness
    Philosophical Studies 174 (10): 2613-2628. 2017.
    An argument for the eponymous conclusion is given through a series of hypothetical syllogisms, the most basic of which is as follows: morality is necessary for self-respect; self-respect is necessary for happiness; therefore, morality is necessary for happiness. Some of the most obvious objections are entertained and rejected.
  •  626
    Virtues are excellences
    Ratio 35 (1): 49-60. 2021.
    One of the few points of unquestioned agreement in virtue theory is that the virtues are supposed to be excellences. The best way to understand the project of "virtue ethics" is to understand this claim as the idea that the virtues always yield correct moral action and, therefore, that we cannot be “too virtuous”. In other words, the virtues cannot be had in excess or “to a fault”. If we take this seriously, however, it yields the surprising conclusion that many traits which have been traditiona…Read more
  •  607
    The Character of the Hypocrite
    Journal of Philosophical Research 43 69-82. 2018.
    A distinction is made between acting hypocritically and the character trait of being a hypocrite. The former is understood as resulting from the employment of a double standard in order to obtain a wrongful advantage, while a particular problem with the latter is that hypocrites do not give trustworthy testimony.
  •  587
    Tracking Eudaimonia
    Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 10 (2). 2018.
    A basic challenge to naturalistic moral realism is that, even if moral properties existed, there would be no way to naturalistically represent or track them. Here, the basic structure for a tracking account of moral epistemology is given in empirically respectable terms, based on a eudaimonist conception of morality. The goal is to show how this form of moral realism can be seen as consistent with the details of evolutionary biology as well as being amenable to the most current understanding of …Read more
  •  576
    Moral Point of View (2nd ed.)
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Blackwell. 2013.
  •  307
    Naturalistic Moral Realism and Evolutionary Biology
    Philosophies 7 (1): 2. 2021.
    Perhaps the most familiar understanding of “naturalism” derives from Quine, understanding it as a continuity of empirical theories of the world as described through the scientific method. So, it might be surprising that one of the most important naturalistic moral realists, Philippa Foot, rejects standard evolutionary biology in her justly lauded _Natural Goodness_. One of her main reasons for this is the true claim that humans can flourish (eudaimonia) without reproducing, which she claims cann…Read more
  •  263
    Error Theory and the Concept of Morality
    Metaphilosophy 44 (4): 451-469. 2013.
    Error theories about morality often take as their starting point the supposed queerness of morality, and those resisting these arguments often try to argue by analogy that morality is no more queer than other unproblematic subject matters. Here, error theory (as exemplified primarily by the work of Richard Joyce) is resisted first by arguing that it assumes a common, modern, and peculiarly social conception of morality. Then error theorists point out that the social nature of morality requires o…Read more
  •  246
    The Axiology of Pain and Pleasure
    Journal of Value Inquiry 1-24. forthcoming.
    There is little more common in ethics than to think pain is intrinsically bad and pleasure is intrinsically good. A Humean-style error theory of the axiology of pain and pleasure is developed against these commonsense claims. We defend the thesis that the value of pain and pleasure is always contingent and only instrumental. We survey prominent theories of both intrinsic value and pain/pleasure, all of which assume that pain and pleasure are intrinsically valuable. We base our error theory o…Read more
  •  230
    Two dogmas of metaethics
    Philosophical Studies 132 (3): 439-466. 2007.
    The two dogmas at issue are the Humean dogma that “‘is’ statements do not imply ‘ought’ statements” and the Kantian dogma that “‘ought’ statements imply ‘can’” statements. The extant literature concludes these logically contradict each other. On the contrary, it is argued here that while there is no derivable formal contradiction, the juxtaposition of the dogmas manifests a philosophical disagreement over how to understand the logic of prescriptions. This disagreement bears on how to understand …Read more
  •  225
    Justice as a Self‐Regarding Virtue
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (1): 46-64. 2010.
  •  212
    Virtue epistemology and the epistemology of virtue
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 23-43. 2000.
    The ancient Greeks almost universally accepted the thesis that virtues are skills. Skills have an underlying intellectual structure , and having a particular skill entails understanding the relevant logos. possessing a general ability to diagnose and solve problems . as well as having appropriate experience. Two implications of accepting this thesis for moral epistemology and epistemology in general are considered. Thinking of virtues as skills yields a viable virtue epistemology in which moral …Read more
  •  200
    Humility Is Not A Virtue
    In Mark Alfano, Michael Patrick Lynch & Alessandra Tanesini (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Humility, Routledge. pp. 36-46. 2021.
  •  192
    Function, Fitness, Flourishing
    In Paul Bloomfield & David Copp (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Moral Realism, Oxford University Press. pp. 264-292. 2023.
  •  169
    Epistemic Temperance
    American Philosophical Quarterly 56 (2): 109-124. 2019.
    The idea of epistemic temperance is introduced and explicated through a discussion of Plato's understanding of it. A variety of psychological and epistemic phenomena are presented which arise due to epistemic intemperance, or the inappropriate influence of conations on cognition. Two cases familiar to philosophers, self-deception and racial prejudice, are discussed as the result of epistemic intemperance though they are not typically seen as having a common cause. Finally, epistemic temperance i…Read more
  •  163
    Archimedeanism and Why Metaethics Matters
    Oxford Studies in Metaethics 4 283-302. 2009.
  •  144
    Prescriptions Are Assertions: An Essay on Moral Syntax
    American Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1). 1998.
  •  138
    Virtue Epistemology and the Epistemology of Virtue
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 23-43. 2000.
    The ancient Greeks almost universally accepted the thesis that virtues are skills. Skills have an underlying intellectual structure (logos), and having a particular skill entails understanding the relevant logos. possessing a general ability to diagnose and solve problems (phronesis). as well as having appropriate experience. Two implications of accepting this thesis for moral epistemology and epistemology in general are considered. Thinking of virtues as skills yields a viable virtue epistemolo…Read more
  •  134
    Is There Moral High Ground?
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 41 (4): 511-526. 2003.
  •  131
    Morality and Self-Interest (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    The volume will act as a useful collection of scholarship by top figures, and as a resource and course book on an important topic.
  •  126
    The Rules of "Goodness": An Essay on Moral Semantics
    American Philosophical Quarterly 40 (3). 2003.
  •  108
    The Skills of Justice
    In Ellen Fridland & Pavase Carlotta (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Skills and Expertise, Rutledge. pp. 460-475. 2021.
  •  100
    Moral Reality
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    We typically assume that the standard for what is beautiful lies in the eye of the beholder. Yet this is not the case when we consider morality; what we deem morally good is not usually a matter of opinion. Such thoughts push us toward being realists about moral properties, but a cogent theory of moral realism has long been an elusive philosophical goal. Paul Bloomfield here offers a rigorous defense of moral realism, developing an ontology for morality that models the property of being morally …Read more
  •  93
    Of Goodness and Healthiness: A Viable Moral Ontology
    Philosophical Studies 87 (3): 309-332. 1997.
  •  88
    The harm of immorality
    Ratio 21 (3): 241-259. 2008.
    A central problem in moral theory is how it is to be defended against those who think that there is no harm in being immoral, and that immorality can be in one's self-interest, assuming the perpetrator is not caught and punished. The argument presented here defends the idea that being immoral prevents one from having self-respect. If it makes sense to think that one cannot be happy without self-respect, then the conclusion follows that one cannot be both immoral and happy. Immorality is harmful …Read more
  •  84
    On human rights * by James Griffin (review)
    Analysis 71 (1): 195-197. 2011.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  82
    Good To Be Bad?
    Think 14 (40): 51-55. 2015.
  •  78
    Dennett's misremenberings
    Philosophia 26 (1-2): 207-218. 1998.