•  28
    Lying and Deceit
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Blackwell. 2013.
  •  11
    One can have faith in someone, believe in someone and trust someone, and these notions seem closely related. Any account of faith should then address its relation to trust and belief. Like trust, faith can similarly have propositional and relational forms. One can have faith that God is good and faith in God; one can trust that another will do something and trust them to do it. Starting from a comparison between these forms of faith and trust, this paper proposes a philosophical analysis of fait…Read more
  •  31
    Losing the rose tinted glasses: neural substrates of unbiased belief updating in depression
    with Neil Garrett, Tali Sharot, Christoph W. Korn, Jonathan P. Roiser, and Raymond J. Dolan
    Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8. 2014.
  •  24
    What Are We Doing When We Are Training?
    Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 13 (3-4): 348-362. 2019.
    ABSTRACTAmateur and professional sportspersons, Bernard Suits proposed, are differentiated by their attitude towards their sport. For the amateur, competition is a game done for its own sake, while...
  •  27
    The presumption of assurance
    Synthese 199 (3-4): 6391-6406. 2021.
    According to the Assurance Theory of testimony, in telling an audience something, a speaker offers their assurance that what is told is true, which is something like their guarantee, or promise, of truth. However, speakers also tell lies and say things they do not have the authority to back up. So why does understanding tellings to be a form of assurance explain how tellings can provide a reason for belief? This paper argues that reasons come once it is recognised that tellings are trusted. And …Read more
  •  451
    Really Trying or Merely Trying
    Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 41 (3): 363-380. 2014.
    We enjoy first-person authority with respect to a certain class of actions: for these actions, we know what we are doing just because we are doing it. This paper first formulates an epistemological principle that captures this authority in terms of trying to act in a way that one has the capacity to act. It then considers a case of effortful action – running a middle distance race – that threatens this principle. And proposes the solution of changing the metaphysics of action: one can keep hold …Read more
  •  24
    Collective and extended knowledge
    Philosophical Issues 32 (1): 200-213. 2022.
    Philosophical Issues, EarlyView.
  •  49
    Communicating your point of view
    European Journal of Philosophy 30 (2): 661-675. 2021.
    European Journal of Philosophy, Volume 30, Issue 2, Page 661-675, June 2022.
  •  71
    The Exchange of Words
    Philosophical Review 130 (1): 167-171. 2021.
  •  69
    Thinking about Knowing
    Mind 113 (450): 390-394. 2004.
  •  79
    Good Knowledge, Bad Knowledge
    Mind 112 (446): 346-349. 2003.
  •  41
    The nature and rationality of conversion
    European Journal of Philosophy 27 (4): 821-836. 2019.
    European Journal of Philosophy, EarlyView.
  •  39
    Indirect Communication, Authority, and Proclamation as a Normative Power
    Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 40 (1): 147-179. 2019.
  •  15
    The Philosophy of Trust (edited book)
    with Thomas Simpson
    Oxford University Press. 2017.
    Trust is central to our social lives. We know by trusting what others tell us. We act on that basis, and on the basis of trust in their promises and implicit commitments. So trust underpins both epistemic and practical cooperation and is key to philosophical debates on the conditions of its possibility. It is difficult to overstate the significance of these issues. On the practical side, discussions of cooperation address what makes society possible—of how it is that life is not a Hobbesian war …Read more
  •  50
    Can we agree to disagree?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 39 (2): 282-285. 2008.
  •  99
    Giving the Benefit of the Doubt
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 26 (2): 139-155. 2018.
    Faced with evidence that what a person said is false, we can nevertheless trust them and so believe what they say – choosing to give them the benefit of the doubt. This is particularly notable when the person is a friend, or someone we are close to. Towards such persons, we demonstrate a remarkable epistemic partiality. We can trust, and so believe, our friends even when the balance of the evidence suggests that what they tell us is false. And insofar as belief is possible, it is also possible t…Read more
  •  148
    On Dreaming and Being Lied To
    Episteme 2 (3): 149-159. 2006.
    As sources of knowledge, perception and testimony are both vulnerable to sceptical arguments. To both arguments a Moorean response is possible: both can be refuted by reference to particular things known by perception and testimony. However, lies and dreams are different possibilities and they are different in a way that undercuts the plausibility of a Moorean response to a scepticism of testimony. The condition placed on testimonial knowledge cannot be trivially satisfied in the way the Moorean…Read more
  •  89
    Collective Testimony and Collective Knowledge
    Ergo: An Open Access Journal of Philosophy 5. 2018.
    Testimony is a source of knowledge. On many occasions, the explanation of one’s knowing that p is that a speaker, S, told one that p. Our testimonial sources—the referents of ‘S’—can be other individuals, and they can be collectives; that is, in addition to learning from individuals, we learn things from committees, commissions, councils, clubs, teams, research groups, departments, administrations, churches, states and other social groups. North Korea might make a declaration about its missile p…Read more
  •  24
    Lying and Deception: Theory and Practice (review)
    Ethics 121 (4): 799-803. 2011.
  •  134
    Cooperation and trust in conversational exchanges
    Theoria 23 (1): 23-34. 2008.
    A conversation is more than a series of disconnected remarks because it is conducted against a background presumption of cooperation. But what makes it reasonable to presume that one is engaged in a conversation? What makes it reasonable to presume cooperation? This paper considers Grice’s two ways of answering this question and argues for the one he discarded. It does so by means of considering a certain problem and analysis of trust.
  •  79
    Review: The Epistemology of Testimony (review)
    Mind 116 (464): 1136-1139. 2007.
  •  201
    The attitude of trust is basic
    Analysis 75 (3): 424-429. 2015.
    Most philosophical discussion of trust focuses on the three-place trust predicate: X trusting Y to φ. This article argues that it is the one-place and two-place predicates – X is trusting, and X trusting Y – that are fundamental.
  •  367
    Norms of Trust
    In Adrian Haddock, Alan Millar & Duncan Pritchard (eds.), Social Epistemology, Oxford University Press. 2010.
    Should we tell other people the truth? Should we believe what other people tell us? This paper argues that something like these norms of truth-telling and belief govern our production and receipt of testimony in conversational contexts. It then attempts to articulate these norms and determine their justification. More fully specified these norms prescribe that speakers tell the truth informatively, or be trustworthy, and that audiences presume that speakers do this, or trust. These norms of trus…Read more
  •  357
    Two-Stage Reliabilism, Virtue Reliabilism, Dualism and the Problem of Sufficiency
    Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 2 (8): 121-138. 2013.
    Social epistemology should be truth-centred, argues Goldman. Social epistemology should capture the ‘logic of everyday practices’ and describe socially ‘situated’ reasoning, says Fuller. Starting from Goldman’s vision of epistemology, this paper aims to argue for Fuller’s contention. Social epistemology cannot focus solely on the truth because the truth can be got in lucky ways. The same too could be said for reliability. Adding a second layer of epistemic evaluation helps only insofar as the re…Read more
  •  248
    The social character of testimonial knowledge
    Journal of Philosophy 97 (11): 581-601. 2000.
    Through communication, we form beliefs about the world, its history, others and ourselves. A vast proportion of these beliefs we count as knowledge. We seem to possess this knowledge only because it has been communicated. If those justifications that depended on communication were outlawed, all that would remain would be body of illsupported prejudice. The recognition of our ineradicable dependence on testimony for much of what we take ourselves to know has suggested to many that an epistemologi…Read more
  •  12
    Replies
    Abstracta 6 (S6): 117-137. 2012.
  •  241
    David Hume's reductionist epistemology of testimony
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 79 (4). 1998.
    David Hume advances a reductionist epistemology of testimony: testimonial beliefs are justified on the basis of beliefs formed from other sources. This reduction, however, has been misunderstood. Testimonial beliefs are not justified in a manner identical to ordinary empirical beliefs; it is true, they are justified by observation of the conjunction between testimony and its truth, it is the nature of the conjunctions that has been misunderstood. The observation of these conjunctions provides us…Read more
  •  49
    Testimonial Knowledge
    Acta Analytica 15 (24): 127-138. 2000.
    The motivation for adopting reductive and anti-reductive theories of testimonial warrant is considered. Whilst both well-motivated neither position can adequately capture the dynamic aspect of the individual knowers relationship to the wider community of knowledge. A hybrid theory of testimony is proposed that attempts to do just this.
  •  271
    On Telling and Trusting
    Mind 116 (464): 875-902. 2007.
    A key debate in the epistemology of testimony concerns when it is reasonable to acquire belief through accepting what a speaker says. This debate has been largely understood as the debate over how much, or little, assessment and monitoring an audience must engage in. When it is understood in this way the debate simply ignores the relationship speaker and audience can have. Interlocutors rarely adopt the detached approach to communication implied by talk of assessment and monitoring. Audiences tr…Read more