•  21
    Davidson's Debt to Anscombe
    Dialogue 59 (2): 219-233. 2020.
    RÉSUMÉL'interprétation de la philosophie pratique de Donald Davidson proposée par Robert Myers représente correctement maints aspects fondamentaux de sa pensée. Myers soutient à juste titre que Davidson évite les incohérences entre la position internaliste, l'objectivité éthique et le modèle croyance-désir en modifiant des éléments centraux de ce modèle, et que l'alternative proposée par Davidson rend légitime l'extension des arguments de l'interprétation et de la triangulation dans la sphère pr…Read more
  •  261
    The Consequentializing Argument Against...Consequentializing?
    Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 12 253-275. 2022.
    Consequentializing involves both a strategy and conditions for its successful implementation. The strategy takes the features a target theory holds to be relevant to deontic evaluation of actions, and builds them into a counterpart ranking of outcomes. It succeeds if the result is 1) a substantive version of consequentialism that 2) yields the same deontic verdicts as the target theory. Consequentializers typically claim and their critics allow that all plausible alternative theories can be c…Read more
  •  171
    Davidson’s Debt to Anscombe
    Dialogue 59 (2): 219-233. 2020.
    Robert Myers’ interpretation of Davidson’s practical philosophy gets Davidson right in many fundamental respects. He rightly argues that Davidson avoids inconsistencies among internalism, ethical objectivity, and the belief-desire theory by modifying central elements of the Humean belief-desire theory, and that Davidson’s alternative legitimizes the extension of his interpretation and triangulation arguments into the practical sphere. But at a crucial fork in the interpretive road Myers loses hi…Read more
  •  1159
    Whose Problem Is Non-Identity?
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 12 (6): 699-730. 2014.
    Teleological theories of reason and value, upon which all reasons are fundamentally reasons to realize states of affairs that are in some respect best, cannot account for the intuition that victims in non-identity cases have been wronged. Many philosophers, however, reject such theories in favor of alternatives that recognize fundamentally non-teleological reasons, second-personal reasons that reflect a moral significance each person has that is not grounded in the teleologist’s appeal to outco…Read more
  •  166
    Evaluator-relative consequentialists frequently endorse the traditional doing-allowing distinction. Yet their endorsement of this traditional distinction only serves to clear the way for their argument against a more fundamental doing-allowing distinction, an argument that one never ought to do something when this will allow something worse to happen. Unlike the case against its more traditional counterpart, the case against this deeper doing-allowing distinction can draw for support upon wide…Read more
  •  439
    Exiting The Consequentialist Circle: Two Senses of Bringing It About
    Analytic Philosophy 60 (2): 130-163. 2019.
    Consequentialism is a state of affairs centered moral theory that finds support in state of affairs centered views of value, reason, action, and desire/preference. Together these views form a mutually reinforcing circle. I map an exit route out of this circle by distinguishing between two different senses in which actions can be understood as bringing about states of affairs. All actions, reasons, desires, and values involve bringing about in the first, deflationary sense, but only some appea…Read more
  •  620
    Consequentialism and the Standard Story of Action
    The Journal of Ethics 22 (1): 25-44. 2018.
    I challenge the common picture of the “Standard Story” of Action as a neutral account of action within which debates in normative ethics can take place. I unpack three commitments that are implicit in the Standard Story, and demonstrate that these commitments together entail a teleological conception of reasons, upon which all reasons to act are reasons to bring about states of affairs. Such a conception of reasons, in turn, supports a consequentialist framework for the evaluation of action, upo…Read more
  •  36
    How weakness of the will is possible
    Mind 101 (401): 85-88. 1992.
  •  294
    Comments on Douglas Portmore’s Commonsense Consequentialism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (1): 225-232. 2014.
  •  4
    Paradox of Deontology
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Wiley. 2022.
  •  3
    Editorial
    Philosophical Studies 148 (1): 1-1. 2010.
  •  26
    A Kantian rationale for desire-based justification
    Philosophers' Imprint 1 1-16. 2001.
    This paper demonstrates that a rationale for a circumscribed form of desire-based justification can be developed out of a contemporary Kantian account as a natural extension of that account. It maintains that certain of Christine Korsgaard's recent arguments establish only that desires must have certain features antithetical to instrumentalism in order to justify. Other arguments purport to establish the standard (stronger) result: that because desires do not have these features, they cannot jus…Read more
  •  36
    Deontology
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Blackwell. 2013.
  •  665
    "Two Senses of Moral Verdict and Moral Overridingness"
    In Mark Timmons (ed.), Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics, Volume 6, Oxford University Press Uk. pp. 215-240. 2011.
    I distinguish two different senses in which philosophers speak of moral verdicts, senses that in turn invite two different senses of moral overridingness. Although one of these senses, that upon which moral verdicts are taken to reflect decisive reasons from a distinctively moral standpoint, currently dominates the moral overridingness debate, my focus is the other sense, upon which moral verdicts are taken to reflect decisive reasons that are distinctively moral. I demonstrate that the recent…Read more
  •  23
    The Many Appetites of Thomas Hobbes
    History of Philosophy Quarterly 7 (4). 1990.
  •  66
    Fairness and beneficence
    Ethics 113 (4): 841-864. 2003.
  •  8
    Scheffler's Argument for Deontology
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74 (2): 118-134. 1993.
  •  52
    Review: R. Jay Wallace: Normativity and the Will (review)
    with D. Scott-Kakures
    Mind 117 (467): 744-750. 2008.
  •  867
    Why Consequentialism’s "Compelling Idea" Is Not
    Social Theory and Practice 43 (1): 29-54. 2017.
    Many consequentialists take their theory to be anchored by a deeply intuitive idea, the “Compelling Idea” that it is always permissible to promote the best outcome. I demonstrate that this Idea is not, in fact, intuitive at all either in its agent-neutral or its evaluator-relative form. There are deeply intuitive ideas concerning the relationship of deontic to telic evaluation, but the Compelling Idea is at best a controversial interpretation of such ideas, not itself one of them. Because the…Read more
  •  10
    Beyond Consequentialism
    Oxford University Press UK. 2009.
    Consequentialism, the theory that morality requires us to promote the best overall outcome, is the default alternative in contemporary moral philosophy, and is highly influential in public discourses beyond academic philosophy. Paul Hurley argues that current discussions of the challenge consequentialism tend to overlook a fundamental challenge to consequentialism. The standard consequentialist account of the content of morality, he argues, cannot be reconciled to the authoritativeness of moral …Read more
  •  479
    Consequentializing and Deontologizing: Clogging the Consequentialist Vacuum"
    Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics 3 123-153. 2013.
    That many values can be consequentialized – incorporated into a ranking of states of affairs – is often taken to support the view that apparent alternatives to consequentialism are in fact forms of consequentialism. Such consequentializing arguments take two very different forms. The first is concerned with the relationship between morally right action and states of affairs evaluated evaluator-neutrally, the second with the relationship between what agents ought to do and outcomes evaluated eval…Read more
  •  57
    Sellars's ethics: Variations on Kantian themes
    Philosophical Studies 101 (2-3): 291-324. 2000.
    In this essay I attempt to tease out and assess two arguments that pervade Sellars's writings on the practical sphere. The first is an argument that categorical reasonableness must be a part of any adequate account of practical reason. The second argues that, nonetheless, the Kantian's strong connection between morality and practical reasonableness cannot be defended. I argue that the former argument is a powerful and ingenious defense of a role for something more than hypothetical reasonablenes…Read more
  •  77
    Desire, Judgment, and Reason: Exploring the Path not Taken
    The Journal of Ethics 11 (4): 437-463. 2007.
    At the outset of The Possibility of Altruism Thomas Nagel charts two paths out of the fundamental dilemma confronting metaethics. The first path rejects the claim that a persuasive account of the motivational backing of ethical judgments must involve an agent’s desires. But it is the second path, a path that Nagel charts but does not himself take, that is the focus of this essay. This path retains the standard account, upon which all motivation involves desire, but denies that desires are given …Read more