•  2
    Decisions in Dynamic Settings
    PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1): 438-449. 1986.
    The expected utility of an option for a decision maker is defined with respect to probability and utility functions that represent the decision maker’s beliefs and desires. Therefore, as the decision maker’s beliefs and desires change, the expected utility of an opinion may change. Some options are such that their realizations change beliefs and desires in ways that change the expected utilities of the options. If a decision is made among options that include one or more of these special options…Read more
  •  55
    Exclusion from the social contract
    Politics, Philosophy and Economics 10 (2): 148-169. 2011.
    Does rational bargaining yield a social contract that is efficient and so inclusive? A core allocation, that is, an allocation that gives each coalition at least as much as it can get on its own, is efficient. However, some coalitional games lack a core allocation, so rationality does not require one in those games. Does rationality therefore permit exclusion from the social contract? I replace realization of a core allocation with another type of equilibrium achievable in every coalitional game…Read more
  •  21
    Like many theorists before him, Paul Weirich has set out to find the Holy Grail of classical game theory: the solution concept that identifies the uniquely rational solution to every non-cooperative game. In this book, he reports an intermediate stage in his quest. He cannot actually identify the unique solution for every game but, he believes, he has found a new concept of equilibrium that is a necessary property of that solution.
  •  6
    The received view of framing
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45. 2022.
    The received view of framing has multiple interpretations. I flesh out an interpretation that is more open-minded about framing effects than the extensionality principle that Bermúdez formulates. My interpretation attends to the difference between preferences held all things considered and preferences held putting aside some considerations. It also makes room for decision principles that handle cases without a complete all-things-considered preference-ranking of options.
  •  10
    AFTERWORDS Criticism and Countertheses
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (3): 327-328. 1981.
  •  12
    An agent often does not have precise probabilities or utilities to guide resolution of a decision problem. I advance a principle of rationality for making decisions in such cases. To begin, I represent the doxastic and conative state of an agent with a set of pairs of a probability assignment and a utility assignment. Then I support a decision principle that allows any act that maximizes expected utility according to some pair of assignments in the set. Assuming that computation of an option's e…Read more
  •  31
    Rational Responses to Risks
    Oxford University Press. 2020.
    A philosophical account of risk, such as this book provides, states what risk is, which attitudes to it are rational, and which acts affecting risks are rational. Attention to the nature of risk reveals two types of risk, first, a chance of a bad event, and, second, an act’s risk in the sense of the volatility of its possible outcomes. The distinction is normatively significant because different general principles of rationality govern attitudes to these two types of risk. Rationality strictl…Read more
  •  113
    This book review describes and evaluates Issac Levi's views about belief revision.
  •  22
    Coordination and Hyperrationality
    ProtoSociology 35 197-214. 2018.
    Margaret Gilbert (1990) argues that although the rationality of the agents in a standard coordination problem does not suffice for their coordination, a social convention of coordination, understood as the agents’ joint acceptance of a principle requiring their coordination, does the job. Gilbert’s argument targets agents rational in the game-theoretic sense, which following Sobel (1994: Chap. 14), I call hyperrational agents. I agree that hyperrational agents may fail to coordinate in some case…Read more
  •  22
    Change in the Decision Sciences
    Lato Sensu: Revue de la Société de Philosophie des Sciences 5 (1): 13-19. 2018.
    A common type of change in science occurs as theorists generalize a model of a phenomenon by removing some idealizations of the model. This type of change occurs in the decision sciences and also in the normative branch of the decision sciences that treats rational choice. After presenting a general ac-count of model generalization, the paper illustrates generalization of models in normative decision theory. The principal illustration generalizes a standard model of rational choice by removing t…Read more
  •  39
    Risk as a Consequence
    Topoi 39 (2): 293-303. 2020.
    Expected-utility theory advances representation theorems that do not take the risk an act generates as a consequence of the act. However, a principle of expected-utility maximization that explains the rationality of preferences among acts must, for normative accuracy, take the act’s risk as a consequence of the act if the agent cares about the risk. I defend this conclusion against the charge that taking an act’s consequences to comprehend all the agent cares about trivializes the principle of e…Read more
  •  1
    Probability and Utility for Decision Theory
    Dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles. 1977.
  •  31
    Mean-risk decision analysis
    Theory and Decision 23 (1): 89-111. 1987.
  •  81
    Utility tempered with equality
    Noûs 17 (3): 423-439. 1983.
  •  58
    Calibration
    In Henk W. de Regt (ed.), Epsa Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009, Springer. pp. 415--425. 2009.
    Abner Shimony argues that degrees of belief satisfy the axioms of probability because their epistemic goal is to match estimates of objective probabilities. Because the estimates obey the axioms of probability, degrees of belief must also obey them to reach their epistemic goal. This calibration argument meets some objections, but with a few revisions it can surmount those objections. It offers a good alternative to the Dutch book argument for compliance with the probability axioms. The defense …Read more
  •  10
    Intrinsic Utility’s Compositionality
    Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (3): 545--563. 2015.
  •  77
    Thomas Mark on works of virtuosity
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 40 (3): 327-328. 1982.
    This paper proposes some amendments to Thomas Mark's account of virtuosity.
  •  12
    Conditionalization and Evidence
    Journal of Critical Analysis 8 (1): 15-18. 1979.
  •  1
    Theory and Evidence (review)
    Philosophical Topics 12 (2): 294-299. 1981.
  •  115
    Belief and acceptance
    In Ilkka Niiniluoto, Matti Sintonen & Jan Wolenski (eds.), Handbook of Epistemology, Kluwer Academic. pp. 499--520. 2004.
    The attitudes of belief and acceptance are similar but differ in important respects such as their relation to degree of belief.
  •  20
    From rationality to coordination
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (2): 179-180. 2003.
    Game theory's paradoxes stimulate the study of rationality. Sometimes they motivate the revising of standard principles of rationality. Other times they call for revising applications of those principles or introducing supplementary principles of rationality. I maintain that rationality adjusts its demands to circumstances, and in ideal games of coordination it yields a payoff-dominant equilibrium.
  •  34
    Auguste Comte, John Stuart Mill, et l'economie politique
    Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy 8 (1): 40-53. 1996.
    none.
  •  33
    Decision When Desires Are Uncertain
    Bowling Green Studies in Applied Philosophy 3 69-75. 1981.
    An agent in a decision problem may not know the goals that should guide selection of an option. Accommodating this ignorance require methods that supplement expected utility theory.
  •  8
    Preference
    In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, Blackwell. 2013.
    Decision theory relies on an account of preference. Some accounts are behaviorist and others are mentalistic. The account used affects the explanatory power of decision theory.
  •  71
    A computer simulation runs a model generating a phenomenon under investigation. For the simulation to be explanatory, the model has to be explanatory. The model must be isomorphic to the natural system that realizes the phenomenon. This paper elaborates the method of assessing a simulation's explanatory power. Then it illustrates the method by applying it to two simulations in game theory. The first is Brian Skyrms's (1990) simulation of interactive deliberations. It is intended to explain the e…Read more
  • Joseph Y. Halpern, Reasoning about Uncertainty (review)
    Philosophy in Review 24 333-336. 2004.
    Reviews Joseph Halpern's book with special attention to his points about conditionals.