•  15
    The Metaphysics of Consciousness (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2010.
    What is consciousness? What is the place of consciousness in nature? These and related questions occupy a prominent place in contemporary studies in metaphysics and philosophy of mind, often involving complex interdisciplinary connections between philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence, biology and cognitive neuroscience. At the same time, these questions play a fundamental role in the philosophies of great thinkers of the past such as, among others, Plotinus, Descartes, Leibniz, Kant, W…Read more
  •  8
    By his own account, Leibniz first encountered the True Intellectual System of the Universe of the Cambridge Platonist Ralph Cudworth during his visit to Rome in the spring of 1689, although the work itself had been published just over a decade earlier in 1678. Leibniz would later report to Cudworth’s daughter, Damaris Masham, that he had been delighted to see the wisdom of the ancients “accompanied by solid reflections”. He had certainly taken the book seriously, devoting sufficient attention to…Read more
  •  7
    Book reviews (review)
    with Michael John Petry, Andrew Pyle, G. H. R. Parkinson, Charles Webster, Nicholas Jolley, Jean‐Michel Vienne, Desmond Clarke, David McNaughton, Vere Chappell, W. H. Brock, and A. F. Griaznov
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (2): 161-199. 1994.
  •  5
    Book reviews (review)
    with T. L. S. Sprigge, Gregorio Piaia, Guido Giglioni, John W. Yolton, Franck Lessay, Richard Kroll, Alan P. F. Sell, J. P. Day, and Ross Harrison
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 4 (1): 165-206. 1996.
  •  2
    Book reviews (review)
    with J. A. Sheppard, Jean‐Louis Breteau, Karl Schuhmann, Dermot Moran, Laura Benítez Grobet, Steven Nadler, Andrew Pyle, John Marshall, Alan P. F. Sell, Emily Michael, Ralph Walker, Graham Bird, Giuseppe Micheli, Gianluigi Oliveri, and Mario Ricciardi
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 6 (3): 473-514. 1998.
    Duns Scotus, Metaphysician. William A. Frank and Allan B. Wolter. Purdue University Press 1995, pp. 224 £27.50 Hb. ISBN 1–55753–071–8 £13.19 Pb. ISBN 1–55753–072–6 Plato in Renaissance England. Sears Jayne. Dordrecht, Boston & London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1995, pp. 197 Dfl. 190.00, $122.00, £80.00 hb. ISBN 0–7923–3060–9 Mechanismus und Subjektivität in der Philosophie von Thomas Hobbes. Michael Esfeld. Frommann‐Holzboog, Stuttgart‐Bad Cannstatt 1995, pp. 434. ISBN 3–7728–1699–1 Descartes,…Read more
  •  15
    Relational Space and Places of Value
    History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 14 (1): 89-106. 2011.
    Drawing on a Leibnizian panpsychist ontology of living beings that have a body and a soul, this paper outlines a theory of space based on the perceptual and appetitive relations among these creatures’ souls. In parallel with physical space founded on relations among bodies subject to efficient causation, teleological space results from relations among souls subject to final causation and is described qualitatively in terms of creatures’ pleasure and pain, wellbeing and happiness. Particular plac…Read more
  • The Metaphysics of Consciousness: Volume 67 (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2010.
    What is consciousness? What is the place of consciousness in nature? These and related questions occupy a prominent place in contemporary studies in metaphysics and philosophy of mind, often involving complex interdisciplinary connections between philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence, biology and cognitive neuroscience. At the same time, these questions play a fundamental role in the philosophies of great thinkers of the past such as, among others, Plotinus, Descartes, Leibniz, Kant, W…Read more
  • Leibniz's monadological positive aesthetics
    In Pauline Phemister & Jeremy William Dunham (eds.), Monadologies, Routledge. 2018.
  •  1
    Monadologies (edited book)
    Routledge. 2018.
  •  37
    The Leibniz-Stahl controversy (book review)
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 26 (6): 1238-1241. 2018.
  •  35
    Substance and force: or why it matters what we think
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 25 (3): 526-546. 2017.
    Leibniz believed the ‘true concept of substance’ is found in ‘the concept of forces or powers’. Accordingly, he conceived monadic substances as metaphysically primitive forces whose modifications manifest both as monads’ appetitions and perceptions and as derivative forces in monads’ organic bodies. Relationships between substances, and in particular the ethical relationships that hold between rational substances, are also foregrounded by Leibniz’s concept of substances as forces. In section one…Read more
  •  13
    Process-relational Philosophy (review)
    Process Studies 39 (1): 195-199. 2010.
  • A Locke Dictionary (review)
    Locke Newsletter 25 89-94. 1994.
  •  74
    Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz stand out as the great 17th century rationalist philosophers who sought to construct a philosophical system in which theological and philosophical foundations serve to explain the physical, mental and moral universe. In her new book Pauline Phemister explores their contribution to the development of modern philosophy.
  •  418
    Leibniz's Monadological Positive Aesthetics
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (6): 1214-1234. 2015.
    One of the most intriguing – and arguably counter-intuitive – doctrines defended by environmental philosophers is that of positive aesthetics, the thesis that all of nature is beautiful. The doctrine has attained philosophical respectability only comparatively recently, thanks in no small part to the work of Allen Carlson, one of its foremost defenders. In this paper, we argue that the doctrine can be found much earlier in the work of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz who devised and defended a version …Read more
  •  4
    Kenneth Winkler (ed.) John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 6 (3): 494-494. 1998.
  •  7
    An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    In his Essay, John Locke sets out his theory of knowledge and how we acquire it. He shows how all our ideas are grounded in human experience and analyses the extent of our knowledge of ourselves and the world. This new abridgement uses P. H. Nidditch's authoritative text to make an accessible edition of Locke's masterpiece.
  •  1
    Descartes and Leibniz
    In Brandon Look (ed.), Continuum Companion to Leibniz, Continuum. pp. 14-29. 2011.
  • Relational Space and Places of Value
    In Emily Brady & Pauline Phemister (eds.), Transformative Values: Human-Environment Relations in Theory and Practice, Springer. pp. 17-30. 2012.
    This is a revised and shortened version of ‘Relational Space and Places of Value’, Logical Analysis and History of Philosophy, 14 (2011), 89-106.
  •  22
    Process-relational Philosophy (review)
    Process Studies 39 (1): 195-199. 2010.
  •  33
    Monadologies: an historical overview
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 23 (6): 1023-1032. 2015.
    This introductory overview comprises a brief account of Leibniz's own monadology; a discussion of the reception of his philosophy up to Kant; and a short overview of the monadologies developed after Kant's first Critique, made via a summary of key points raised in this guest issue, highlighting recurrent themes, which include questions of historiography