•  1
    Intuitionism
    with David McNaugton
    In Hugh LaFollette & Ingmar Persson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, Blackwell. pp. 287-310. 2013.
    What makes an action morally obligatory, the one that we are morally required to do? Different moral theories give different answers to this question. The simplest answer would be that just one consideration is relevant to the rightness of an action. Act‐consequentialism (which we will refer to as “consequentialism,” unless otherwise indicated) is a popular and influential theory that claims just this. On this view, the only morally relevant consideration is the effect an action will have on the…Read more
  •  1
    Holism about value
    with D. McNaugton
    In Vojko Strahovnik, Matjaz Potrc & Mark Norris Lance (eds.), Challenging Moral Particularism, Routledge. pp. 166--184. 2008.
  •  4
    Decision Theory and Degree of Belief
    In Stephen P. Turner & Paul A. Roth (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Blackwell. 2003.
    This chapter contains sections titled: The Theory of von Neumann and Morgenstern Rational Choice Theory Prescription and Description Ramsey's Theory Dutch Books and the Epistemic Objection Savage's Theory What is Preference and Why is it More Basic than Qualitative Probability? Context Freedom and the Transitivity of Preference The Causal Independence of Acts and Events The Constant Act Problem Allais's and Ellsberg's Examples Conclusion.
  •  5
    Davidson's Measurement‐Theoretic Analogy
    In Ernie Lepore & Kurt Ludwig (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Donald Davidson, Blackwell. 2013.
    Donald Davidson is famous for, among other things, his theory of radical interpretation – an account of how it is that we can attribute meanings to people's words, and contents to their mental states, based on an apparent paucity of evidence. This account is infused with ideas from, and applications of, the general theory of measurement, as well as one specific instance of that theory – decision theory. In addition, however, Davidson also applies measurement theory – in the form of his “measurem…Read more
  •  60
    Radical Interpretation and Logical Pluralism
    Topoi 38 (2): 277-289. 2019.
    I examine Quine’s and Davidson’s arguments to the effect that classical logic is the one and only correct logic. This conclusion is drawn from their views on radical translation and interpretation, respectively. I focus on the latter, but I first address, independently, Quine’s argument to the effect that the ‘deviant’ logician, who departs from classical logic, is merely changing the subject. Regarding logical pluralism, the question is whether there is more than one correct logic. I argue that…Read more
  •  27
    Naturalism And Normativity: Reply to McNaughton and Rawling
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 104 (1): 187-203. 2004.
    McNaughton and Rawling's anti-reductionist intentions are to be welcomed, but are not well served by their continuing adherence to a neo-Humean notion of the 'descriptive'. Their too-willing acceptance of this notion is reflected in a denial of appropriate dialectical weight to considerations about the way 'pattern' disappears from the domain of value when we try to characterize the constituent features of the latter in non-evaluative terms. The need for a satisfactory account of the immanence o…Read more
  •  9
    Book Reviews (review)
    with George Huxley, John J. Ansbro, Maeve Cooke, John Preston, Garin V. Dowd, John Bussanich, Flash Q. Fiasco, José Luis Bermúdez, Lucie A. Antoniol, João Branquinho, Jérôme Dokic, Peter König, Iseult Honohan, and Paul S. Miklowitz
    Humana Mente 3 (2): 346-382. 1995.
  •  167
    Naturalism and Normativity
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1). 2003.
    Simon Blackburn can be seen as challenging those committed to sui generis moral facts to explain the supervenience of the moral on the descriptive. We (like perhaps Derek Parfit) hold that normative facts in general are sui generis. We also hold that the normative supervenes on the descriptive, and we here endeavour to answer the generalization of Blackburn's challenge. In the course of pursuing this answer, we suggest that Frank Jackson's descriptivism rests on a conception of properties inappr…Read more
  • Benefits, holism, and the aggregation of value
    In Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred Dycus Miller & Jeffrey Paul (eds.), Utilitarianism: the aggregation question, Cambridge University Press. 2009.
  •  51
    Blameworthiness and Dependence
    Philosophical Quarterly 74 (1): 110-124. 2023.
    Some recent accounts of blameworthiness present this property as response-dependent: an agent is blameworthy, they say, if and only if, and (if so) in virtue of the fact that, it is fitting to respond to her with a certain blaming emotion. Given the explanatory aim of these views, the selected emotion cannot be said simply to appraise its object as blameworthy. We argue that articulation of the appraisal in other terms suggested by proponents yields a failure of the coextension required by the a…Read more
  •  198
    Reason to Feel Guilty
    In Andreas Carlsson (ed.), Self-Blame and Moral Responsibility, Cambridge University Press. pp. 217-36. 2022.
    Let F be a fact in virtue of which an agent, S, is blameworthy for performing an act of A-ing. We advance a slightly qualified version of the following thesis: (Reason) F is (at some time) a reason for S to feel guilty (to some extent) for A-ing. Leaving implicit the qualification concerning extent, we claim as well: (Desert) S's having this reason suffices for S’s deserving to feel guilty for A-ing. We also advance a third thesis connecting desert of feeling guilty with the fitti…Read more
  •  270
    True Blame
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 101 (3): 736-749. 2023.
    1. We sometimes angrily confront, pointedly ostracize, castigate, or denounce those whom we think have committed moral offences. Conduct of this kind may be called blaming behaviour. When genuine,...
  •  13
    Rationality and Dynamic Choice: Foundational Explorations (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (184): 390-393. 1996.
  •  18
    The Routledge Handbook of Translation and Philosophy (edited book)
    with Philip Wilson
    Routledge. 2018.
    The Routledge Handbook of Translation and Philosophy presents the first comprehensive, state of the art overview of the complex relationship between the field of translation studies and the study of philosophy. The book is divided into four sections covering discussions of canonical philosophers, central themes in translation studies from a philosophical perspective, case studies of how philosophy has been translated and illustrations of new developments. With twenty-nine chapters written by int…Read more
  •  42
    I—David McNaughton and Piers Rawling: Descriptivism, Normativity and the Metaphysics of Reasons
    with David McNaughton
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1): 23-45. 2003.
    Simon Blackburn can be seen as challenging those committed to sui generis moral facts to explain the supervenience of the moral on the descriptive. We hold that normative facts in general are sui generis. We also hold that the normative supervenes on the descriptive, and we here endeavour to answer the generalization of Blackburn's challenge. In the course of pursuing this answer, we suggest that Frank Jackson's descriptivism rests on a conception of properties inappropriate to discussions of no…Read more
  •  222
    Scanlon suggests a buck-passing account of goodness. To say that something is good is not to give a reason to, say, favour it; rather it is to say that there are such reasons. When it comes to wrongness, however, Scanlon rejects a buck-passing account: to say that j ing is wrong is, on his view, to give a sufficient moral reason not to j. Philip Stratton-Lake 2003 argues that Scanlon can evade a redundancy objection against his (Scanlon’s) view of wrongness by adopting a buck-passing account of …Read more
  •  31
    The exchange paradox, finite additivity, and the principle of dominance
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 71 49-76. 2000.
  •  10
    No Title available: Reviews
    Economics and Philosophy 14 (2): 342-349. 1998.
  •  135
    Conditional and Conditioned Reasons
    Utilitas 14 (2): 240. 2002.
    This paper is a brief reponse to some of Douglas Portmore's criticisms of our version of the agent-relative/agent-neutral distinction
  • Akeel Bilgrami, Belief and Meaning
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 3 (2): 353-354. 1995.
  •  250
    The making/evidential reason distinction
    Analysis 71 (1): 100-102. 2011.
    Stephen Kearns and Daniel Star have made the following interesting proposal concerning the relation between practical reasons and evidence : Necessarily: A fact F is a reason for you to φ iff F is evidence that you ought to φ We're not sure about this. Although moving from left to right might be OK, the converse is problematic. For example, the fact that your reliable friend told you that you have overriding moral reason to φ is …
  •  24
    Duty, rationality, and practical reasons
    In Piers Rawling & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 110--131. 2004.
    McNaughton and Rawling present a view on which practical reasons are facts, such as the fact that the rubbish bin is full. This is a non-normative fact, but it is a reason for you to do something, namely take the rubbish out. They see rationality as a matter of consistency. And they see duty as neither purely a matter of rationality nor of practical reason: on the one hand, the rational sociopath is immoral; but, on the other, morality does not require that we always act on the weightiest moral …Read more
  •  143
    Deontology and Agency
    The Monist 76 (1): 81-100. 1993.
    Any adequate account of the distinction between consequentialist and deontological moral systems must take account of the central place given to constraints in the latter. Constraints place limits on what each of us may do in the pursuit of any goal, including the maximisation of the good. There is some debate, however, both over how constraints are to be characterised, and over the rationale for their inclusion in a moral system. Some authors view constraints as agent-relative: a constraint sup…Read more
  •  44
    Expected Utility, Ordering, and Context Freedom
    Economics and Philosophy 13 (1): 79. 1997.
    The context-free weak ordering principle is viewed by many as a cornerstone of rational choice theory. McClennen, for example, claims that this principle is one of a pair on which '[t]he theory of rational choice and preference, as it has been developed in the past few decades by economists and decision theorists, rests', and Sen characterizes a version of context freedom as ‘a very basic requirement of rational choice’. But this principle is certainly not uncontroversial: there are examples of …Read more
  • The Logical Status of Conditionalization and its Role in Confirmation Commentary
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 71 77-94. 2000.