•  4
    Intuitions as Evidence in Philosophy
    In Green Mitchell & Michel Jan G. (eds.), William Lycan on Mind, Meaning, and Method, Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 257-272. 2024.
    Philosophers advance hypotheses, and occasionally those hypotheses are to some extent justified on the basis of some evidence. But what sorts of things can serve as such evidence, and how can they do so? These are the central questions of Lycan’s book On Evidence in Philosophy. There, he claims that one sort of thing that can serve as evidence in philosophy is “intuition.” But what, in Lycan’s view, are intuitions, and what is it about intuitions that enable them to function as evidence in philo…Read more
  •  4
    Wright on Internalism, Externalism, and Perceptual Skepticism
    In Ori Beck & Miloš Vuletić (eds.), Empirical Reason and Sensory Experience, Springer Verlag. pp. 329-331. 2024.
    You regard yourself as enjoying genuine sensory engagement with what philosophers call “the external world”, viz., a spatio-temporal world that exists independently of your consciousness. For instance, you see the computer screen before you, you feel the chair against your back, you hear dogs barking outside your room, etc.
  •  62
    Inquiry, research, and articulate free agency
    Philosophical Studies. forthcoming.
    My cat Percy and I both engage in inquiry. For example, we both might wonder where the food is, and look around systematically in an effort to find the food. Indeed, we might even recruit others to help us search for the food, and so engage in collaborative inquiry concerning the location of the food. But such inquiry, even when collaborative, does not amount to _research_. Why not? What distinguishes research from the kinds of inquiry in which Percy and I can both engage? You might think that r…Read more
  •  28
    In defense of disjunctivism
    In Adrian Haddock & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: perception, action, knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 311--29. 2008.
    Right now, I see a computer in front of me. Now, according to current philosophical orthodoxy, I could have the very same perceptual experience that I’m having right now even if I were not seeing a computer in front of me. Indeed, such orthodoxy tells us, I could have the very same experience that I’m having right now even if I were not seeing anything at all in front of me, but simply suffering from a hallucination. More generally, someone can have the very same perceptual experience no matter …Read more
  •  75
    In defense of disjunctivism
    In Adrian Haddock & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: perception, action, knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 311--29. 2008.
    Right now, I see a computer in front of me. Now, according to current philosophical orthodoxy, I could have the very same perceptual experience that I’m having right now even if I were not seeing a computer in front of me. Indeed, such orthodoxy tells us, I could have the very same experience that I’m having right now even if I were not seeing anything at all in front of me, but simply suffering from a hallucination. More generally, someone can have the very same perceptual experience no matter …Read more
  • In defence of disjunctivism
    In Adrian Haddock & Fiona Macpherson (eds.), Disjunctivism: perception, action, knowledge, Oxford University Press. 2008.
  •  128
    Classical foundationalism and the dawning light
    Philosophical Studies 1-17. forthcoming.
  •  43
    Correction to Credence and belief
    Philosophical Studies 180 (10): 3215-3215. 2023.
  •  1
    How is thinking possible?
    In James Conant & Jesse M. Mulder (eds.), Reading Rödl: on Self-consciousness and objectivity. 2024.
  •  75
    Correction To: Credence and belief
    Philosophical Studies 180 (9): 2895-2895. 2023.
  •  131
    From Inputs to Beliefs
    Analysis 82 (4): 707-716. 2022.
    What you believe is typically responsive to what you perceive, what you recall, what inferences you’ve made and various other factors. Let’s use the term ‘input.
  • The motivating power of the a priori obvious
    In Karen Jones & François Schroeter (eds.), The Many Moral Rationalisms, Oxford University Press. 2018.
  •  234
    Credence and belief
    Philosophical Studies 180 (2): 429-438. 2022.
  •  46
    Book symposium on Ernest sosa’s epistemic explanations
    Philosophical Topics 49 (2): 385-404. 2021.
    Ernest Sosa’s new monograph, Epistemic Explanations, develops an important new account of epistemic evaluation, epistemic normativity, and the explanatory role of these. The first two sections of the present paper develop an interpretation of Sosa’s metaphysics of the mental states of rational agents as a version of hylomorphism. The second half of the paper uses this hylomorphic view to argue that Sosa can account for differences among the various kinds of knowledge by appeal to nothing more th…Read more
  •  130
    Capacitism and the transparency of evidence
    Mind and Language 37 (2): 219-226. 2022.
    Susanna Schellenberg develops a unified account—“capacitism”—of perceptual content, phenomenology, and epistemic force. In this paper, I raise questions about her arguments for a capacitist account of evidential force, and then challenge her claim that such an account, even if correct, demands that our evidence be less than fully transparent to us.
  •  2
    The Transparency of Inference
    In Anders Nes & Timothy Hoo Wai Chan (eds.), Inference and Consciousness, Routledge. 2019.
  •  98
    Rationality, Success, and Luck
    Acta Analytica 37 (1): 57-71. 2021.
    Rationality, whatever exactly it demands of us, promotes success, whatever exactly that is. Some philosophers interpret that slogan as something that can provide them with a way of reductively explaining the demands of rationality by appeal to some independently intelligible notion of success: being rational, they might say, is just having whatever property it is that promotes success. Other philosophers may interpret the same slogan as something that can provide them with a way of reductively e…Read more
  •  423
    What evidence do you have?
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59 (1): 89-119. 2008.
    Your evidence constrains your rational degrees of confidence both locally and globally. On the one hand, particular bits of evidence can boost or diminish your rational degree of confidence in various hypotheses, relative to your background information. On the other hand, epistemic rationality requires that, for any hypothesis h, your confidence in h is proportional to the support that h receives from your total evidence. Why is it that your evidence has these two epistemic powers? I argue that …Read more
  •  120
    Mario De Caro and David Macarthur, eds., Naturalism in Question
    Philosophical Review 116 (4): 657-663. 2007.
  •  871
    The Basing Relation
    Philosophical Review 128 (2): 179-217. 2019.
    Sometimes, there are reasons for which we believe, intend, resent, decide, and so on: these reasons are the “bases” of the latter, and the explanatory relation between these bases and the latter is what I will call “the basing relation.” What kind of explanatory relation is this? Dispositionalists claim that the basing relation consists in the agent’s manifesting a disposition to respond to those bases by having the belief, intention, resentment, and so on, in question. Representationalists clai…Read more
  •  133
    An evidentialist account of hinges
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 15): 3577-3591. 2019.
    Wittgenstein’s On Certainty is sometimes read as providing a response to the skeptical puzzle from closure, according to which our commitment to the trustworthiness of our evidence is not itself evidentially grounded. In this paper, I argue both that this standard reading of Wittgenstein is incorrect, and that a more accurate reading of Wittgenstein provides us with a more plausible solution to the Closure Puzzle.
  •  189
  •  40
    Current Controversies In Epistemology (edited book)
    Routledge. 2014.
    Epistemology is one of the oldest, yet still one of the most active, areas of philosophical research today. There currently exists many annotated tomes of primary sources, and a handful of single-authored introductions to the field, but there is no book that captures epistemology’s dynamic growth and lively debates for a student audience. In this volume, eight leading philosophers debate four topics central to recent research in epistemology: The A Priori: C. S. I. Jenkins and Michael Devitt The…Read more
  •  293
    Luminosity and the safety of knowledge
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (4). 2004.
    In his recent Knowledge and its Limits, Timothy Williamson argues that no non-trivial mental state is such that being in that state suffices for one to be in a position to know that one is in it. In short, there are no “luminous” mental states. His argument depends on a “safety” requirement on knowledge, that one’s confident belief could not easily have been wrong if it is to count as knowledge. We argue that the safety requirement is ambiguous; on one interpretation it is obviously true but usele…Read more
  •  47
    Access Internalism and the Guidance Deontological Conception of Justification
    American Philosophical Quarterly 53 (2): 155-168. 2016.
    Historically, prominent proponents of the guidance deontological conception of epistemic justification have thought that the guidance deontological conception entails access internalism. Alvin Goldman has argued that this is not so, and that there is no good argument from the guidance deontological conception of justification to access internalism. This paper refutes Goldman's argument. If the guidance deontological conception of epistemic justification is correct, then so is access internalism.
  •  255
    What is an inference
    Philosophical Issues 23 (1): 388-407. 2013.