•  94
    Phaedo 100B3-9
    Mnemosyne 68 (3): 393-412. 2015.
  •  62
    Two Annotated Bibliographies on the Presocratics
    with Sylvia Berryman and Alexander P. D. Mourelatos
    Ancient Philosophy 15 (2): 471-494. 1995.
  •  56
    Commentary On Fine
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 28 (1): 147-157. 2013.
    In discussing Gail Fine’s contribution, Sharma challenges the idea that the pseudo-Platonic Sisyphus can productively be interpreted using the philosophical devices of Plato’s Meno. Sharma then explores another approach to the Sisyphus, which involves reading the dialogue as an attack on the tendency to assimilate deliberation to theoretical inquiry and, relatedly, as an attempt to call attention to the practical skills that are uniquely involved in deliberation. Sharma ends by speculating that …Read more
  •  45
    Xenophon's Socrates on Justice and Well-being
    Ancient Philosophy 40 (1): 19-40. 2020.
  •  32
    Virtue and Self-Interest in Xenophon’s Memorabilia 3.9.4–5
    Classical Quarterly 68 (1): 79-90. 2018.
    Are people at bottom motivated entirely by self-interest? Or do they act only sometimes out of self-interest, and sometimes for other reasons—say, to help out a friend for her own sake, with no expectation of being benefitted in return? Scholars have often thought they could discern in the works of classical Greek thinkers a commitment to psychological egoism, the thesis that one is motivated to act only by considerations of the expected benefits and harms that will accrue to oneself. For instan…Read more
  •  32
    Xenophon's Socrates on Harming Enemies
    Ancient Philosophy 39 (2): 253-265. 2019.
  •  26
    Platonic Inquiry
    Polis 34 (1): 147-155. 2017.
  •  14
    Eristic Combat at Euthydemus 285e–286b
    with Russell E. Jones
    Australasian Philosophical Review 3 (2): 167-175. 2019.
    ABSTRACT M.M. McCabe argues that in Plato’s Euthydemus, Dionysodorus and Euthydemus hold a view she calls ‘chopped logos’. Chopped logos implies that nothing said is false, or opposed to any other statement, or entailed by any other statement. We focus on a key piece of evidence for chopped logos, the argument concluding that there is no such thing as contradiction (285e9–286b6), and defend a competing interpretation. The argument in question, and the eristic exchanges as a whole, are simply exa…Read more
  •  10
    The Bloomsbury Handbook of Socrates (edited book, 2nd ed.)
    with Russell E. Jones and Nicholas D. Smith
    Bloomsbury Handbooks. 2024.
    This handbook provides detailed philosophical analysis of the life and thought of Socrates across fifteen in-depth chapters. Each chapter engages with a central aspect of the rich tradition of Socratic studies and, after surveying the state of scholarship, points the way forward to new directions of interpretation. A leading team of scholars present dynamic readings of Socrates, extracted from the historical context of Plato's dialogues, covering elenchus, irony, ignorance, definitions, pedagogy…Read more
  •  3
  •  1
    The Philosophical Origins of Plato's Theory of Forms
    Dissertation, The University of Texas at Austin. 2001.
    The dissertation analyzes the ontological and epistemological arguments that motivate Plato's theory of Forms. ;The first chapter explains how the word 'ontology' will be used and, in so doing, compares two ways of determining ontological commitments. ;The second chapter argues that Plato subscribes to the first of those two ways. For at 95E--103C of Plato's Phaedo, the theory of Forms is introduced in a context that is best interpreted as embodying a concern with ontological explanation. Schola…Read more
  • Xenophon’s Socrates on Concern for Friends
    with Russell E. Jones
    Thaumàzein: Rivista di Filosofia 9. 2021.
  • Xenophon’s Socrates on Teaching and Learning (2nd ed.)
    with Russell E. Jones
    In Russell E. Jones, Ravi Sharma & Nicholas D. Smith (eds.), The Bloomsbury Handbook of Socrates, Bloomsbury Handbooks. 2024.