•  465
    Moral Fictionalism
    Philosophy Now 82 14-17. 2011.
    Were I not afraid of appearing too philosophical, I should remind my reader of that famous doctrine, supposed to be fully proved in modern times, “That tastes and colours, and all other sensible qualities, lie not in the bodies, but merely in the senses.” The case is the same with beauty and deformity, virtue and vice. This doctrine, however, takes off no more from the reality of the latter qualities, than from that of the former; nor need it give any umbrage either to critics or moralists. Thou…Read more
  •  447
    The Error In 'The Error In The Error Theory'
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (3): 519-534. 2011.
    In his paper ?The Error in the Error Theory?[this journal, 2008], Stephen Finlay attempts to show that the moral error theorist has not only failed to prove his case, but that the error theory is in fact false. This paper rebuts Finlay's arguments, criticizes his positive theory, and clarifies the error-theoretic position
  •  444
    The Myth of Morality
    Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    In The Myth of Morality, Richard Joyce argues that moral discourse is hopelessly flawed. At the heart of ordinary moral judgements is a notion of moral inescapability, or practical authority, which, upon investigation, cannot be reasonably defended. Joyce argues that natural selection is to blame, in that it has provided us with a tendency to invest the world with values that it does not contain, and demands that it does not make. Should we therefore do away with morality, as we did away with ot…Read more
  •  380
    The Evolution of Morality
    Bradford. 2005.
    Moral thinking pervades our practical lives, but where did this way of thinking come from, and what purpose does it serve? Is it to be explained by environmental pressures on our ancestors a million years ago, or is it a cultural invention of more recent origin? In The Evolution of Morality, Richard Joyce takes up these controversial questions, finding that the evidence supports an innate basis to human morality. As a moral philosopher, Joyce is interested in whether any implications follow from…Read more
  •  333
    Moral Fictionalism
    In Mark Eli Kalderon (ed.), Fictionalism in Metaphysics, Oxford University Press. pp. 287-313. 2005.
  •  241
    Preçis of The Evolution of Morality
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (1): 213-218. 2008.
    The Evolution of Morality attempts to accomplish two tasks. The first is to clarify and provisionally advocate the thesis that human morality is a distinct adaptation wrought by biological natural selection. The second is to inquire whether this empirical thesis would, if true, have any metaethical implications.
  •  239
    Moral Reality
    Mind 112 (445): 94-99. 2003.
  •  214
    Is Moral Projectivism Empirically Tractable?
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12 (1). 2009.
    Different versions of moral projectivism are delineated: minimal, metaphysical, nihilistic, and noncognitivist. Minimal projectivism (the focus of this paper) is the conjunction of two subtheses: (1) that we experience morality as an objective aspect of the world and (2) that this experience has its origin in an affective attitude (e.g., an emotion) rather than in perceptual faculties. Both are empirical claims and must be tested as such. This paper does not offer ideas on any specific test proc…Read more
  •  210
    Expressivism and motivation internalism
    Analysis 62 (4): 336-344. 2002.
    The task of this paper is to argue that expressivism [the thesis that moral judgements function to express desires, emotions, or pro/con attitudes] neither implies, nor is implied by, [motivational internalism].
  •  194
    Taking moral skepticism seriously
    Philosophical Studies 168 (3): 843-851. 2014.
  •  187
    Metaethics and the empirical sciences
    Philosophical Explorations 9 (1). 2006.
    What contribution can the empirical sciences make to metaethics? This paper outlines an argument to a particular metaethical conclusion - that moral judgments are epistemically unjustified - that depends in large part on a posteriori premises.
  •  169
    Moral realism and teleosemantics
    Biology and Philosophy 16 (5): 723-31. 2001.
    In a recent article, William F. Harms (2000) argues in a novel way for a form of moral realism. He does not actually argue that moral realism is true, but rather that if morality is the product of natural selection
  •  158
    Irrealism and the Genealogy of Morals
    Ratio 26 (4): 351-372. 2013.
    Facts about the evolutionary origins of morality may have some kind of undermining effect on morality, yet the arguments that advocate this view are varied not only in their strategies but in their conclusions. The most promising such argument is modest: it attempts to shift the burden of proof in the service of an epistemological conclusion. This paper principally focuses on two other debunking arguments. First, I outline the prospects of trying to establish an error theory on genealogical grou…Read more
  •  137
    A World without Values
    Springer. 2009.
    Taking as its point of departure the work of moral philosopher John Mackie (1917-1981), A World Without Values is a collection of essays on moral skepticism by leading contemporary philosophers, some of whom are sympathetic to Mackie s ...
  •  132
    Darwinian ethics and error
    Biology and Philosophy 15 (5): 713-732. 2000.
    Suppose that the human tendency to think of certain actions andomissions as morally required – a notion that surely lies at the heart of moral discourse – is a trait that has been naturallyselected for. Many have thought that from this premise we canjustify or vindicate moral concepts. I argue that this is mistaken, and defend Michael Ruse's view that the moreplausible implication is an error theory – the idea thatmorality is an illusion foisted upon us by evolution. Thenaturalistic fallacy is a…Read more
  •  126
    Cooperation and its Evolution (edited book)
    MIT Press. 2013.
    This collection reports on the latest research on an increasingly pivotal issue for evolutionary biology: cooperation. The chapters are written from a variety of disciplinary perspectives and utilize research tools that range from empirical survey to conceptual modeling, reflecting the rich diversity of work in the field. They explore a wide taxonomic range, concentrating on bacteria, social insects, and, especially, humans. Part I (“Agents and Environments”) investigates the connections of soci…Read more
  •  97
    The Skeptick’s Tale (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 78 (1). 2008.
    Any metaethicist tempted to dismiss a defense of moral intuitionism as too flaky to merit serious attention should think twice. Ethical Intuitionism is a forceful, clear, original, and intelligent piece of philosophy, and Michael Huemer can be proud of his efforts. He proceeds by identifying an exhaustive list of five possible metaethical positions, then knocks down four until only his favored intuitionism remains. One of the advantages of any such “last man standing” strategy is that even the m…Read more
  •  97
    The Fugitive Thought
    Journal of Value Inquiry 34 (4): 463-478. 2000.
    Moral imperatives are claimed to be inescapable. The moral felon who convinces us that he desired to commit his crimes, that he had no desires that the actions thwarted, does not incline us to withdraw our judgment that he did what he ought not to have done. We do not permit him to evade his moral culpability by citing unusual desires or interests. This thesis of moral inescapability seems familiar and yet is notoriously difficult to make sense of. Philippa Foot calls it “the fugitive thought,” …Read more
  •  88
    Morality, schmorality
    In Paul Bloomfield (ed.), Morality and Self-Interest, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    In his contribution to this volume, Paul Bloomfield analyzes and attempts to answer the question “Why is it bad to be bad?” I too will use this question as my point of departure; in particular I want to approach the matter from the perspective of a moral error theorist. This discussion will preface one of the principal topics of this paper: the relationship between morality and self-interest. Again, my main goal is to clarify what the moral error theorist might say on this subject. Against this …Read more
  •  87
    To hold an error theory about morality is to endorse a kind of radical moral skepticism—a skepticism analogous to atheism in the religious domain. The atheist thinks that religious utterances, such as “God loves you,” really are truth-evaluable assertions (as opposed to being veiled commands or expressions of hope, etc.), but that the world just doesn’t contain the items (e.g., God) necessary to render such assertions true. Similarly, the moral error theorist maintains that moral judgments are t…Read more
  •  86
    Review of Kalderon, M.E., Moral Fictionalism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 85 (1): 161-173. 2012.
  •  72
    Reply to ‘On the Validity of a Simple Argument for Moral Error Theory’
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 24 (4): 518-522. 2016.
  •  69
    The accidental error theorist
    Oxford Studies in Metaethics 6 153. 2011.
  •  60
    “Nihilism” (from the Latin “nihil” meaning nothing) is not a well-defined term. One can be a nihilist about just about anything: A philosopher who does not believe in the existence of knowledge, for example, might be called an “epistemological nihilist”; an atheist might be called a “religious nihilist.” In the vicinity of ethics, one should take care to distinguish moral nihilism from political nihilism and from existential nihilism. These last two will be briefly discussed below, only with the…Read more
  •  57
    Why humans judge things to be good
    Biology and Philosophy 19 (5): 809-817. 2004.