-
186Social SoftwareSynthese 132 (3): 187-211. 2002.We suggest that the issue of constructing andverifying social procedures, which we suggestively call socialsoftware, be pursued as systematically as computer software is pursued by computer scientists. Certain complications do arise withsocial software which do not arise with computer software, but thesimilarities are nonetheless strong, and tools already exist which wouldenable us to start work on this important project. We give a variety ofsuggestive examples and indicate some theoretical work…Read more
-
146Game Logic - An OverviewStudia Logica 75 (2): 165-182. 2003.Game Logic is a modal logic which extends Propositional Dynamic Logic by generalising its semantics and adding a new operator to the language. The logic can be used to reason about determined 2-player games. We present an overview of meta-theoretic results regarding this logic, also covering the algebraic version of the logic known as Game Algebra.
-
146Conditional Probability and Defeasible InferenceJournal of Philosophical Logic 34 (1). 2005.We offer a probabilistic model of rational consequence relations (Lehmann and Magidor, 1990) by appealing to the extension of the classical Ramsey-Adams test proposed by Vann McGee in (McGee, 1994). Previous and influential models of nonmonotonic consequence relations have been produced in terms of the dynamics of expectations (Gärdenfors and Makinson, 1994; Gärdenfors, 1993).'Expectation' is a term of art in these models, which should not be confused with the notion of expected utility. The exp…Read more
-
145Sentences, belief and logical omniscience, or what does deduction tell us?Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (4): 459-476. 2008.We propose a model for belief which is free of presuppositions. Current models for belief suffer from two difficulties. One is the well known problem of logical omniscience which tends to follow from most models. But a more important one is the fact that most models do not even attempt to answer the question what it means for someone to believe something, and just what it is that is believed. We provide a flexible model which allows us to give meaning to beliefs in general contexts, including th…Read more
-
143Journal of Philosophical Logic 34, 97-119, 2005.
-
109Vagueness and utility: The semantics of common nouns (review)Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (6). 1994.A utility-based approach to the understanding of vague predicates (VPs) is proposed. It is argued that assignment of truth values to propositions containing VPs entails unjustifiable assumptions of consensus; two models of VP semantics are criticized on this basis: (1) the super-truth theory of Kit Fine (1975), which requires an unlikely consensus on base points; (2) the fuzzy logic of Lotfi Zadeh (1975), on fuzzy truth values of sentences. Pragmatism is held to provide a key: successful behavio…Read more
-
106Relevance Sensitive Non-Monotonic Inference on Belief SequencesJournal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 11 (1): 131-150. 2001.We present a method for relevance sensitive non-monotonic inference from belief sequences which incorporates insights pertaining to prioritized inference and relevance sensitive, inconsistency tolerant belief revision. Our model uses a finite, logically open sequence of propositional formulas as a representation for beliefs and defines a notion of inference from maxiconsistent subsets of formulas guided by two orderings: a temporal sequencing and an ordering based on relevance relations between …Read more
-
101The Logic of Knowledge Based ObligationSynthese 149 (2): 311-341. 2006.Deontic Logic goes back to Ernst Mally’s 1926 work, Grundgesetze des Sollens: Elemente der Logik des Willens [Mally. E.: 1926, Grundgesetze des Sollens: Elemente der Logik des Willens, Leuschner & Lubensky, Graz], where he presented axioms for the notion ‘p ought to be the case’. Some difficulties were found in Mally’s axioms, and the field has much developed. Logic of Knowledge goes back to Hintikka’s work Knowledge and Belief [Hintikka, J.: 1962, Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Lo…Read more
-
97Vague predicates and language gamesTheoria 11 (3): 97-107. 1996.Attempts to give a Logic or Semantics for vague predicates and to defuse the Sorites paradoxes have been largely a failure. We point out yet another problem with these predicates which has not been remarked on before,namely that different people do and must use these predicates in individually different ways. Thus even if there were a semantics for vague predicates, people would not be able to share it. To explain the occurrence nonetheless of these troublesome predicates in language, we propose…Read more
-
94A knowledge based semantics of messagesJournal of Logic, Language and Information 12 (4): 453-467. 2003.We investigate the semantics of messages, and argue that the meaning ofa message is naturally and usefully given in terms of how it affects theknowledge of the agents involved in the communication. We note thatthis semantics depends on the protocol used by the agents, and thus not only the message itself, but also the protocol appears as a parameter in the meaning. Understanding this dependence allows us to give formal explanations of a wide variety of notions including language dependence, impl…Read more
-
72Meeting of the Association for Symbolic Logic, New York City, May 1987Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (4): 1270-1274. 1988.
-
68Probabilistic conditionals are almost monotonicReview of Symbolic Logic 1 (1): 73-80. 2008.One interpretation of the conditional If P then Q is as saying that the probability of Q given P is high. This is an interpretation suggested by Adams (1966) and pursued more recently by Edgington (1995). Of course, this probabilistic conditional is nonmonotonic, that is, if the probability of Q given P is high, and R implies P, it need not follow that the probability of Q given R is high. If we were confident of concluding Q from the fact that we knew P, and we have stronger information R, we c…Read more
-
65Beth definability, interpolation and language splittingSynthese 179 (2). 2011.Both the Beth definability theorem and Craig's lemma (interpolation theorem from now on) deal with the issue of the entanglement of one language L1 with another language L2, that is to say, information transfer—or the lack of such transfer—between the two languages. The notion of splitting we study below looks into this issue. We briefly relate our own results in this area as well as the results of other researchers like Kourousias and Makinson, and Peppas, Chopra and Foo.Section 3 does contain …Read more
-
61Obituary: Horacio Arló-costaEpisteme 9 (2): 89-89. 2012.Editorial Rohit Parikh, Jeffrey Helzner, Episteme, FirstView Article
-
612000-2001 Spring Meeting of the Association for Symbolic LogicBulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (3): 413-419. 2001.
-
61On knowledge and obligationEpisteme 9 (2): 171-188. 2012.This article provides a brief overview of several formal frameworks concerning the relation between knowledge on the one hand, and obligation on the other. We discuss the paradox of the knower, knowledge based obligation, knowingly doing, deontic dynamic epistemology, descriptive obligations, and responsibilities as dynamic epistemology.
-
54Completeness of Certain Bimodal Logics for Subset SpacesStudia Logica 71 (1): 1-30. 2002.Subset Spaces were introduced by L. Moss and R. Parikh in [8]. These spaces model the reasoning about knowledge of changing states.In [2] a kind of subset space called intersection space was considered and the question about the existence of a set of axioms that is complete for the logic of intersection spaces was addressed. In [9] the first author introduced the class of directed spaces and proved that any set of axioms for directed frames also characterizes intersection spaces.We give here a c…Read more
-
52Topological reasoning and the logic of knowledgeAnnals of Pure and Applied Logic 78 (1-3): 73-110. 1996.We present a bimodal logic suitable for formalizing reasoning about points and sets, and also states of the world and views about them. The most natural interpretation of the logic is in subset spaces , and we obtain complete axiomatizations for the sentences which hold in these interpretations. In addition, we axiomatize the validities of the smaller class of topological spaces in a system we call topologic . We also prove decidability for these two systems. Our results on topologic relate earl…Read more
-
52On Kripke's Puzzle about Time and ThoughtIn Kamal Lodaya (ed.), Logic and Its Applications, Springer. pp. 121--126. 2013.
-
48We propose a new relevance sensitive model for representing and revising belief structures, which relies on a notion of partial language splitting and tolerates some amount of inconsistency while retaining classical logic. The model preserves an agent's ability to answer queries in a coherent way using Belnap's four-valued logic. Axioms analogous to the AGM axioms hold for this new model. The distinction between implicit and explicit beliefs is represented and psychologically plausible, computat…Read more
-
39Gems of theoretical computer science, Uwe schöning and Randall PruimJournal of Logic, Language and Information 9 (1): 131-132. 2000.
-
37Ronald Fagin, Joseph Y. Halpern, Yoram Moses, and Moshe Y. Vardi. Reasoning about knowledge. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass., and London1995, xiii + 477 pp (review)Journal of Symbolic Logic 62 (4): 1484-1487. 1997.
-
36Some Generalisations of the Notion of Well OrderingMathematical Logic Quarterly 12 (1): 333-340. 1966.
-
36Vague Predicates and Language GamesTheoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 11 (3): 97-107. 1996.Attempts to give a Logic or Semantics for vague predicates and to defuse the Sorites paradoxes have been largely a failure. We point out yet another problem with these predicates which has not been remarked on before,namely that different people do and must use these predicates in individually different ways. Thus even if there were a semantics for vague predicates, people would not be able to share it. To explain the occurrence nonetheless of these troublesome predicates in language, we propose…Read more
-
35How Far Can We Formalize Language Games?Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook 3 89-100. 1995.I want to start by giving some quotes from Wittgenstein. It is part of his conception of what the foundations of Mathematics are about, a conception which many people have found peculiar and one of my defects is that I am not able to find it peculiar anymore, but find it perfectly sensible
New York City, New York, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Philosophy of Language |
Logic and Philosophy of Logic |