University of Otago
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1987
Acton, Australian Capital Territory, Australia
  •  322
    Personal identity, minimalism, and madhyamaka
    Philosophy East and West 52 (3): 373-385. 2002.
    The publication of Derek Parfit's Reasons and Persons in 1984 revived and reshaped the debate on personal identity in Western philosophy. Not only does Parfit argue forcefully and ingeniously for a revisionary Reductionist theory of persons and their diachronic identity, but he also draws radical normative inferences from such a theory. Along the way he also mentions Indian Buddhist parallels to his own Reductionist theory. Some of these parallels are explored here, while particular attention is…Read more
  •  250
    Virtue ethics and maori ethics
    with John Patterson
    Philosophy East and West 41 (2): 185-202. 1991.
  •  188
    Ineffability, signification and the meaning of life
    Philosophical Papers 39 (2): 239-255. 2010.
    There is an apparent tension between two familiar platitudes about the meaning of life: (i) that 'meaning' in this context means 'value', and (ii) that such meaning might be ineffable. I suggest a way of trying to bring these two claims together by focusing on an ideal of a meaningful life that fuses both the axiological and semantic senses of 'significant'. This in turn allows for the possibility that the full significance of a life might be ineffable not because its axiological significance is…Read more
  •  166
    Buddhism, abortion and the middle way
    Asian Philosophy 10 (2). 2000.
    What have modern Buddhist ethicists to say about abortion and is there anything to be learned from it? A number of writers have suggested that Buddhism (particularly Japanese Buddhism) does indeed have something important to offer here: a response to the dilemma of abortion that is a 'middle way' between the pro-choice and pro-life extremes that have polarised the western debate. I discuss what this suggestion might amount to and present a defence of its plausibility.
  •  155
    Indigenous rights and environmental justice
    Environmental Ethics 20 (4): 377-391. 1998.
    The modern environmental movement has a tradition of respect for indigenous cultures and many environmentalists believe that there are important ecological lessons to be learned from studying the traditional life styles of indigenous peoples. More recently, however, some environmentalists have become more sceptical. This scepticism has been sharpened by current concerns with the cause of indigenous rights. Indigenous peoples have repeatedly insisted on their rights to pursue traditional practice…Read more
  •  154
    Personal Identity, Reductionism and the Necessity of Origins
    with Charles Barton
    Erkenntnis 51 (2-3): 277-294. 1999.
    A thought that we all entertain at some time or other is that the course of our lives might have been very different from the way they in fact have been, with the consequence that we might have been rather different sorts of persons than we actually are. A less common, but prima facie intelligible thought is that we might never have existed at all, though someone rather like us did. Arguably, any plausible theory of personal identity should be able to accommodate both possibilities. Certain curr…Read more
  •  114
    Tolstoy, Death and the Meaning of Life
    Philosophy 60 (232): 231-245. 1985.
    Questions about the meaning of life have traditionally been regarded as being of particular concern to philosophers. It is sometimes complained that contemporary analytic philosophy fails to address such questions, but there do exist illuminating recent discussions of these questions by analytic philosophers.1Perhaps what lurks behind the complaint is a feeling that these discussions are insufficiently close to actual living situations and hence often seem rather thin and bland compared with the…Read more
  •  107
    The Analogical Argument for Animal Pain
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 14 (1): 49-58. 1997.
    Philosophical defenders of animal liberation believe that we have direct duties to animals. Typically a presumption of that belief is that animals have the capacity to experience pain and suffering. Notoriously, however, a strand of Western scientific and philosophical thought has held animals to be incapable of experiencing pain, and even today one frequently encounters in discussions of animal liberation expressions of scepticism about whether animals really experience pain. The Analogical Arg…Read more
  •  102
    Buddhism, euthanasia and the sanctity of life
    Journal of Medical Ethics 22 (5): 309-13. 1996.
    Damien and John Keown claim that there is important common ground between Buddhism and Christianity on the issue of euthanasia and that both traditions oppose it for similar reasons in order to espouse a "sanctity of life" position. I argue that the appearance of consensus is partly created by their failure to specify clearly enough certain key notions in the argument: particularly Buddhism, euthanasia and the sanctity of life. Once this is done, the Keowns' central claims can be seen to be eith…Read more
  •  101
    The momentariness of simples
    Philosophy 79 (3): 435-445. 2004.
    Many philosophers have supposed that while most of the objects in our immediate experience are composed of parts, at some point we must come down to those fundamental impartite objects out of which all partite things are composed: the metaphysical simples (usually conceived of as enduring, even eternal, entities). I consider what reason we have to believe that there really are simples, then we also have good reason to believe in their momentariness.
  •  97
    Death and immortality
    Distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Kluwer Academic Publishers. 1987.
    INTRODUCTION In The World as Will and Representation Schopenhauer writes: Death is the real inspiring genius or Musagetes of philosophy, and for this reason ...
  •  94
    Evil and Human Nature
    The Monist 85 (2): 304-19. 2002.
    One familiar philosophical use of the term ‘evil’ just contrasts it with ‘good’, i.e., something is an evil if it is a bad thing, one of life’s “minuses.” This is the sense of ‘evil’ that is used in posing the traditional theological problem of evil, though it is customary there to distinguish between moral evils and natural evils. Moral evils are those bad things that are caused by moral agents; natural evils are those bad things that are not caused by moral agents. Since the existence of evils…Read more
  •  83
    Musical unity and sentential unity
    British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (2): 97-111. 1999.
  •  82
    Intentionality and self-awareness
    Ratio 16 (3): 222-235. 2003.
    In this essay I defend both the individual plausibility and conjoint consistency of two theses. One is the Intentionality Thesis: that all mental states are intentional . The other is the Self-Awareness Thesis: that if a subject is aware of an object, then the subject is also aware of being aware of that object. I begin by arguing for the individual prima facie plausibility of both theses. I then go on to consider a regress argument to the effect that the two theses are incompatible. I discuss t…Read more
  •  77
    Buddhist idealism and the problem of other minds
    Asian Philosophy 27 (1): 59-68. 2017.
    This essay is concerned with Indian Yogācāra philosophers’ treatment of the problem of other minds in the face of a threatened collapse into solipsism suggested by Vasubandhu’s epistemological argument for idealism. I discuss the attempts of Dharmakīrti and Ratnakīrti to address this issue, concluding that Dharmakīrti is best seen as addressing the epistemological problem of other minds and Ratnakīrti as addressing the conceptual problem of other minds.
  •  72
    Is whatever exists knowable and nameable?
    Philosophy East and West 49 (4): 401-414. 1999.
    Naiyāyikas are fond of a slogan, which often appears as a kind of motto in their texts: "Whatever exists is knowable and nameable." What does this mean? Is it true? The first part of this essay offers a brief explication of this important Nyāya thesis; the second part argues that, given certain plausible assumptions, the thesis is demonstrably false
  •  70
    We (relatively few) Western analytic philosophers who also work on classical Indian philosophy commonly encounter puzzlement or suspicion from our colleagues in Western philosophy because of our Indian interests. The ubiquity of these attitudes is itself revealing of Western conceptions of Indian philosophy, though their origins lie in cultural history often unknown to those who hold them. In the first part of this paper I relate a small but significant slice of that history before going on to d…Read more
  •  69
    Associated with the successful development of computer technology has been an increasing acceptance of computational theories of the mind. But such theories also seem to close the gap between ourselves and machines, threatening traditional notions of our special value as non-physical conscious minds. Prima facie, Sāmkhya-Yoga - the oldest school of classical Indian philosophy, with its dualism between purusa ('self', 'consciousness') and prakrti ('nature', 'matter') - seems a case in point. Howe…Read more
  •  68
    Preferring more pain to less
    Philosophical Studies 93 (2): 213-226. 1999.
  •  64
    Studies in Buddhist Philosophy by Mark Siderits
    Philosophy East and West 68 (1): 1-5. 2017.
    Over the last few decades Mark Siderits has established himself as a leading philosophical interpreter of Indian Buddhist philosophy. He has published widely in this field, but three of his books are particularly well known: his Personal Identity and Buddhist Philosophy, a self-styled "essay in fusion philosophy"; his introductory textbook Buddhism as Philosophy ; and–with Shōryū Katsura–his translation and commentary, Nāgārjuna's Middle Way: Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. Taken together, these three boo…Read more
  •  61
    Our present actions can have effects on future generations - affecting not only the environment they will inherit, but even perhaps their very existence. This raises a number of important moral issues, many of which have only recently received serious philosophical attention. I begin by discussing some contemporary Western philosophical perspectives on the problem of our obligations to future generations, and then go on to consider how these approaches might relate to the classical Indian philos…Read more
  •  60
    John Hick on Faith: A Critique (review)
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 15 (1/2). 1984.
  •  60
    The problem of induction in indian philosophy
    Philosophy East and West 34 (2): 161-174. 1984.
  •  57
    Tolstoy, Death and the Meaning of Life
    Philosophy 60 (232): 231-245. 1985.
    Questions about the meaning of life have traditionally been regarded as being of particular concern to philosophers. It is sometimes complained that contemporary analytic philosophy fails to address such questions, but there do exist illuminating recent discussions of these questions by analytic philosophers.1Perhaps what lurks behind the complaint is a feeling that these discussions are insufficiently close to actual living situations and hence often seem rather thin and bland compared with the…Read more
  •  54
  •  52
    Book reviews and notices (review)
    with Srimati Basu, Heather T. Frazer, Dermot Killingley, James Blumenthal, Anne M. Blackburn, Kees W. Bolle, Donald R. Davis, Mariko Namba Walter, and George W. Spencer
    International Journal of Hindu Studies 6 (3): 319-337. 2002.
  •  51
    Evil and Human Nature
    The Monist 85 (2): 304-319. 2002.
    One familiar philosophical use of the term ‘evil’ just contrasts it with ‘good’, i.e., something is an evil if it is a bad thing, one of life’s “minuses.” This is the sense of ‘evil’ that is used in posing the traditional theological problem of evil, though it is customary there to distinguish between moral evils and natural evils. Moral evils are those bad things that are caused by moral agents; natural evils are those bad things that are not caused by moral agents. Since the existence of evils…Read more
  •  50
    Symbols, icons and stupas
    British Journal of Aesthetics 36 (4): 432-438. 1996.
  •  47
    The bodhisattva paradox
    Philosophy East and West 36 (1): 55-59. 1986.