•  903
    (What) Is Feminist Logic? (What) Do We Want It to Be?
    History and Philosophy of Logic 45 (1): 20-45. 2024.
    ‘Feminist logic’ may sound like an impossible, incoherent, or irrelevant project, but it is none of these. We begin by delineating three categories into which projects in feminist logic might fall: philosophical logic, philosophy of logic, and pedagogy. We then defuse two distinct objections to the very idea of feminist logic: the irrelevance argument and the independence argument. Having done so, we turn to a particular kind of project in feminist philosophy of logic: Valerie Plumwood's feminis…Read more
  •  615
    Comics, Prints, and Multiplicity
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 73 (1): 57-67. 2015.
    Comics comprise a hybrid art form descended from printmaking and mostly made using print technologies. But comics are an art form in their own right and do not belong to the art form of printmaking. We explore some features art comics and fine art prints do and do not have in common. Although most fine art prints and comics are multiple artworks, it is not obvious whether the multiple instances of comics and prints are artworks in their own right. The comparison of comics and fine art prints pro…Read more
  •  518
    Let a thousand flowers Bloom: A tour of logical pluralism
    Philosophy Compass 5 (6): 492-504. 2010.
    Logical pluralism is the view that there is more than one correct logic. In this article, I explore what logical pluralism is, and what it entails, by: (i) distinguishing clearly between relativism about a particular domain and pluralism about that domain; (ii) distinguishing between a number of forms logical pluralism might take; (iii) attempting to distinguish between those versions of pluralism that are clearly true and those that are might be controversial; and (iv) surveying three prominent…Read more
  •  506
    Abstraction and identity
    Dialectica 59 (2). 2005.
    A co-authored article with Roy T. Cook forthcoming in a special edition on the Caesar Problem of the journal Dialectica. We argue against the appeal to equivalence classes in resolving the Caesar Problem.
  •  505
    Response to my critics
    Análisis Filosófico 32 (1): 69-97. 2012.
    During the Winter of 2011 I visited SADAF and gave a series of talks based on the central chapters of my manuscript on the Yablo paradox. The following year, I visited again, and was pleased and honored to find out that Eduardo Barrio and six of his students had written ‘responses’ that addressed the claims and arguments found in the manuscript, as well as explored new directions in which to take the ideas and themes found there. These comments reflect my thoughts on these responses (also collec…Read more
  •  400
    The Propositional Logic of Frege’s Grundgesetze: Semantics and Expressiveness
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 5 (6). 2017.
    In this paper we compare the propositional logic of Frege’s Grundgesetze der Arithmetik to modern propositional systems, and show that Frege does not have a separable propositional logic, definable in terms of primitives of Grundgesetze, that corresponds to modern formulations of the logic of “not”, “and”, “or”, and “if…then…”. Along the way we prove a number of novel results about the system of propositional logic found in Grundgesetze, and the broader system obtained by including identity. In …Read more
  •  349
    Comments on Patricia Blanchette's Book: Frege's Conception of Logic (review)
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 3 (7). 2015.
    All contributions included in the present issue were originally presented at an ‘Author Meets Critics’ session organised by Richard Zach at the Pacific Meeting of the American Philosophical Association in San Diego in the Spring of 2014.
  •  347
    Patterns of paradox
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 69 (3): 767-774. 2004.
    We begin with a prepositional languageLpcontaining conjunction (Λ), a class of sentence names {Sα}αϵA, and a falsity predicateF. We (only) allow unrestricted infinite conjunctions, i.e., given any non-empty class of sentence names {Sβ}βϵB,is a well-formed formula (we will useWFFto denote the set of well-formed formulae).The language, as it stands, is unproblematic. Whether various paradoxes are produced depends on which names are assigned to which sentences. What is needed is a denotation functi…Read more
  •  317
    The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 54 (2): 347-352. 2003.
  •  268
    What’s Wrong with Tonk
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 34 (2). 2005.
    In “The Runabout Inference Ticket” AN Prior (1960) examines the idea that logical connectives can be given a meaning solely in virtue of the stipulation of a set of rules governing them, and thus that logical truth/consequence
  •  235
    Curry, Yablo and duality
    Analysis 69 (4): 612-620. 2009.
    The Liar paradox is the directly self-referential Liar statement: This statement is false.or : " Λ: ∼ T 1" The argument that proceeds from the Liar statement and the relevant instance of the T-schema: " T ↔ Λ" to a contradiction is familiar. In recent years, a number of variations on the Liar paradox have arisen in the literature on semantic paradox. The two that will concern us here are the Curry paradox, 2 and the Yablo paradox. 3The Curry paradox demonstrates that neither negation nor a falsi…Read more
  •  219
    The T-schema is not a logical truth
    Analysis 72 (2): 231-239. 2012.
    It is shown that the logical truth of instances of the T-schema is incompatible with the formal nature of logical truth. In particular, since the formality of logical truth entails that the set of logical truths is closed under substitution, the logical truth of T-schema instances entails that all sentences are logical truths
  •  206
    What is a Truth Value And How Many Are There?
    Studia Logica 92 (2): 183-201. 2009.
    Truth values are, properly understood, merely proxies for the various relations that can hold between language and the world. Once truth values are understood in this way, consideration of the Liar paradox and the revenge problem shows that our language is indefinitely extensible, as is the class of truth values that statements of our language can take – in short, there is a proper class of such truth values. As a result, important and unexpected connections emerge between the semantic paradoxes…Read more
  •  205
    Vagueness and mathematical precision
    Mind 111 (442): 225-247. 2002.
    One of the main reasons for providing formal semantics for languages is that the mathematical precision afforded by such semantics allows us to study and manipulate the formalization much more easily than if we were to study the relevant natural languages directly. Michael Tye and R. M. Sainsbury have argued that traditional set-theoretic semantics for vague languages are all but useless, however, since this mathematical precision eliminates the very phenomenon (vagueness) that we are trying to …Read more
  •  199
    Knights, knaves and unknowable truths
    Analysis 66 (1): 10-16. 2006.
  •  177
    In (2002) I argued that Gupta and Belnap’s Revision Theory of Truth (1993) has counterintuitive consequences. In particular, the pair of sentences: (S1) At least one of S1 and S2 is false. (S2) Both of S1 and S2 are false.1 is pathological on the Revision account. There is one, and only one, assignment of truth values to {(S1), (S2)} that make the corresponding Tarski..
  •  173
    Impure Sets Are Not Located: A Fregean Argument
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 1 (3): 219-229. 2012.
    It is sometimes suggested that impure sets are spatially co-located with their members (and hence are located in space). Sets, however, are in important respects like numbers. In particular, sets are connected to concepts in much the same manner as numbers are connected to concepts—in both cases, they are fundamentally abstracts of (or corresponding to) concepts. This parallel between the structure of sets and the structure of numbers suggests that the metaphysics of sets and the metaphysics of …Read more
  •  169
    A number of formal constraints on acceptable abstraction principles have been proposed, including conservativeness and irenicity. Hume’s Principle, of course, satisfies these constraints. Here, variants of Hume’s Principle that allow us to count concepts instead of objects are examined. It is argued that, prima facie, these principles ought to be no more problematic than HP itself. But, as is shown here, these principles only enjoy the formal properties that have been suggested as indicative of …Read more
  •  155
    There is No Paradox of Logical Validity
    Logica Universalis 8 (3-4): 447-467. 2014.
    A number of authors have argued that Peano Arithmetic supplemented with a logical validity predicate is inconsistent in much the same manner as is PA supplemented with an unrestricted truth predicate. In this paper I show that, on the contrary, there is no genuine paradox of logical validity—a completely general logical validity predicate can be coherently added to PA, and the resulting system is consistent. In addition, this observation lead to a number of novel, and important, insights into th…Read more
  •  150
    The state of the economy: Neo-logicism and inflation
    Philosophia Mathematica 10 (1): 43-66. 2002.
    In this paper I examine the prospects for a successful neo–logicist reconstruction of the real numbers, focusing on Bob Hale's use of a cut-abstraction principle. There is a serious problem plaguing Hale's project. Natural generalizations of this principle imply that there are far more objects than one would expect from a position that stresses its epistemological conservativeness. In other words, the sort of abstraction needed to obtain a theory of the reals is rampantly inflationary. I also in…Read more
  •  147
    Do Comics Require Pictures? Or Why Batman #663 Is a Comic
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 69 (3): 285-296. 2011.
  •  145
    Kit Fine, The Limits of Abstraction Oxford, Clarendon Press, 2002, cloth 18.99/US $25.00 ISBN: 0-19-924618-1 (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (4): 791-800. 2004.
    Critical Notice of The Limits of abstraction by Kit Fine, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2002, pp.216. ISBN 9780191567261
  •  140
    Hintikka's Revolution: The Priciples of Mathematics Revisited (review)
    with Stewart Shpiro
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (2): 309-316. 1998.
  •  137
    If A then B: How the World Discovered Logic
    History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (3): 301-303. 2014.
    If A then B: How the World Discovered Logic is a historically oriented introduction to the basic notions of logic. In particular, and in the words of the authors, it is focused on the idea that ‘lo...
  •  136
    Conservativeness, Stability, and Abstraction
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 63 (3): 673-696. 2012.
    One of the main problems plaguing neo-logicism is the Bad Company challenge: the need for a well-motivated account of which abstraction principles provide legitimate definitions of mathematical concepts. In this article a solution to the Bad Company challenge is provided, based on the idea that definitions ought to be conservative. Although the standard formulation of conservativeness is not sufficient for acceptability, since there are conservative but pairwise incompatible abstraction principl…Read more
  •  135
    The Paradox of Adverbs
    Analysis 75 (4): 559-561. 2015.