•  81
    Brentano was surely mistaken, however, in thinking that bearing a relation to something nonexistent marks only the mental. Given any sort of purpose, it might not get fulfilled, hence might exhibit Brentano's relation, and there are many natural purposes, such as the purpose of one's stomach to digest food or the purpose of one's protective eye blink reflex to keep out the sand, that are not mental, nor derived from anything mental. Nor are stomachs and reflexes "of" or"about" anything. A reply …Read more
  •  51
    On cognitive luck: Externalism in an evolutionary frame
    In Martin Carrier & Peter Machamer (eds.), Mindscapes: Philosophy, Science, and the Mind, University of Pittsburgh Press. 1997.
    Steven Pinker (1995) chides the educated layman for imagining Darwin's theory to go this way (the vertical lines are "begats"): [Figure #1] Pinker says, "evolution did not make a ladder; it made a bush" (p. 343), and he gives us the following diagrams instead, showing how it went, in increasing detail, down to us
  •  20
    What has Natural Information to Do with Intentional Representation?
    In D. Walsh (ed.), Evolution, Naturalism and Mind, Cambridge University Press. pp. 105-125. 2001.
    "According to informational semantics, if it's necessary that a creature can't distinguish Xs from Ys, it follows that the creature can't have a concept that applies to Xs but not Ys." (Jerry Fodor, The Elm and the Expert, p.32)
  •  106
    Pushmi-pullyu representations
    In James E. Tomberlin (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, Ridgeview Publishing. pp. 185-200. 1987.
    A list of groceries, Professor Anscombe once suggested, might be used as a shopping list, telling what to buy, or it might be used as an inventory list, telling what has been bought (Anscombe 1957). If used as a shopping list, the world is supposed to conform to the representation: if the list does not match what is in the grocery bag, it is what is in the bag that is at fault. But if used as an inventory list, the representation is supposed to conform to the world: if the list does not match wh…Read more
  •  14
    Styles of rationality
    In Susan Hurley & Matthew Nudds (eds.), Rational Animals?, Oxford University Press. 2006.
    By whatever general principles and mechanisms animal behavior is governed, human behavior control rides piggyback on top of the same or very similar mechanisms. We have reflexes. We can be conditioned. The movements that make up our smaller actions are mostly caught up in perception-action cycles following perceived Gibsonian affordances. Still, without doubt there are levels of behavior control that are peculiar to humans. Following Aristotle, tradition has it that what is added in humans is ra…Read more
  •  3
    Observations of S * → π + π - in ψ decay
    with G. Gidal, G. Goldhaber, J. G. Guy, G. S. Abrams, M. S. Alam, C. A. Blocker, A. Blondel, A. Boyarski, M. Breidenbach, D. L. Burke, W. C. Carithers, W. Chinowsky, M. W. Coles, S. Cooper, W. E. Dieterle, J. B. Dillon, J. Dorehbosch, J. M. Dorfan, M. W. Eaton, Fe G. J., M. E. B. Franklin, G. Hanson, K. A. Hayes, T. Himel, D. G. Hitlin, R. Hollebeek, W. Innes, J. Jaros, Jenni P., A. D. Johnson, J. A. Kadyk, A. J. Lankford, R. R. Larsen, V. Luth, M. E. Nelson, C. Y. Pang, Patrick J. F., B. Richter, A. Roussarie, D. L. Scharre, R. H. Schindler, R. F. Schwitters, J. L. Siegrist, J. Strait, H. Taureg, M. Tonutti, G. H. Trilling, E. N. Vella, R. A. Vidal, I. Videau, J. M. Weiss, and H. Zaccone
    Copious production of S* decaying into π+π- is observed in ψ decay. MeV, consistent with the parameters extracted from couplede channel; fits to pheripheral π+π- and K+K- production experiments. The inclusive branching ratio for ψ → S* + X is found to be %. © 1981.
  •  2
    A study of the decay τ - →π - μ τ
    with C. A. Blocker, J. M. Dorfan, G. S. Abrams, M. S. Alam, A. Blondel, A. M. Boyarski, M. Breidenbach, D. L. Burke, W. C. Carithers, W. Chinowsky, M. W. Coles, S. Cooper, W. E. Dieterle, J. B. Dillon, J. Dorenbosch, M. W. Eaton, G. J. Feldman, M. E. B. Franklin, G. Gidal, G. Goldhaber, G. Hanson, K. G. Hayes, T. Himel, D. G. Hitlin, R. J. Hollebeek, W. R. Innes, J. A. Jaros, Jenni P., A. D. Johnson, J. A. Kadyk, A. J. Lankford, R. R. Larsen, Levi M., V. Lüth, M. E. Nelson, C. Y. Pang, Patrick J. F., M. L. Perl, B. Richter, A. Roussarie, D. L. Scharre, R. H. Schindler, R. F. Schwitters, J. L. Siegrist, J. Strait, H. Taureg, M. Tonutti, G. H. Trilling, and E. N. Vella
    We present a high statistics measurement of the branching ratio for the decay τ-→π-μτ using data obtained with the Mark II detector at the SLAC e+e- storage ring SPEAR. We have used events from the center-of-mass energy region 3.52 to 6.7 GeV to determine that B=0.117±0.004±0.018. From electron-muon events in the same data sample, we have determined that B B=0.66±0.03±0.11. We present measurements of the mass and spin of the τ and the mass of the τ neutrino based, for the first time, on a hadron…Read more
  •  2
    Observation of the radiative transition ψ → γE
    with D. L. Scharre, G. H. Trilling, G. S. Abrams, M. S. Alam, C. A. Blocker, A. Blondel, A. M. Boyarski, M. Breidenbach, D. L. Burke, W. C. Carithers, W. Chinowsky, M. W. Coles, S. Cooper, W. E. Dieterle, J. B. Dillon, J. Dorenbosch, J. M. Dorfan, M. W. Eaton, G. J. Feldman, M. E. B. Franklin, G. Gidal, G. Goldhaber, G. Hanson, K. G. Hayes, T. Himel, D. G. Hitlin, R. J. Hollebeek, W. R. Innes, J. A. Jaros, Jenni P., A. D. Johnson, J. A. Kadyk, A. J. Lankford, R. R. Larsen, V. Lüth, M. E. Nelson, C. Y. Pang, Patrick J. F., M. L. Perl, B. Richter, A. Roussarie, R. H. Schindler, R. F. Schwitters, J. L. Siegrist, J. Strait, H. Taureg, M. Tonutti, E. N. Vella, and R. A. Vidal
    We have observed a radiative transition from the ψ to a state decaying into KSK±π∓, with mass M = 1.44-0.015+0.01 GeV/c2 and width Γ = 0.05-0.02+0.03 GeV/c2. We tentatively identify this state as the E. Assuming that this state is an isospin singlet, we have determined the branching fraction product B × B = × 10-3. © 1980.
  •  9
    What has natural information to do with intentional representation?
    In Denis M. Walsh (ed.), Naturalism, Evolution and the Mind, Cambridge University Press. pp. 105-125. 2001.
    There is, indeed, a form of informational semantics that has this verificationist implication. The original definition of information given in Dretske's Knowledge and the Flow of Information (1981, hereafter KFI), when employed as a base for a theory of intentional representation or "content," has this implication. I will argue that, in fact, most of what an animal needs to know about its environment is not available as natural information of this kind. It is true, I believe, that there is one f…Read more
  •  2
    Reading mother nature's mind
    In Don Ross, Andrew Brook & David Thompson (eds.), Dennett’s Philosophy: A Comprehensive Assessment, Mit Press. 2000.
    I try to focus our differences by examining the relation between what Dennett has termed "the intentional stance" and "the design stance." Dennett takes the intentional stance to be more basic than the design stance. Ultimately it is through the eyes of the intentional stance that both human and natural design are interpreted, hence there is always a degree of interpretive freedom in reading the mind, the purposes, both of Nature and of her children. The reason, or at least a reason, is that int…Read more
  • Ramsey 311,314 Rembrandt 388 Rosenberg, Alexander xxi Ross, WD. 274
    with Nathan Salmon, Andrew Melnyk, Trenton Merricks, John Stuart Mill, Matt Millen, Piet Mondrian, Isaac Newton, David Owens, and David Papineau
    In Jaegwon Kim (ed.), Supervenience, Ashgate. pp. 397. 2002.
  • Daniel C. Dennett
    with Saul Kripke Haugeland, Hilary Putnam, Richard Rorty, Jerome Feldman Brown, D. K. Modrak, Carolyn Ristau, Jonathan Schull, Stephen White, and Andrew Woodfield
    In Paul K. Moser & J. D. Trout (eds.), Contemporary Materialism: A Reader, Routledge. 1995.
  •  155
    Biofunctions: Two paradigms
    In André Ariew, Robert Cummins & Mark Perlman (eds.), Functions: New Essays in the Philosophy of Psychology and Biology, Oxford University Press. pp. 113-143. 2002.
  •  1066
    Biosemantics
    Journal of Philosophy 86 (6): 281--297. 1989.
    " Biosemantics " was the title of a paper on mental representation originally printed in The Journal of Philosophy in 1989. It contained a much abbreviated version of the work on mental representation in Language Thought and Other Biological Categories. There I had presented a naturalist theory of intentional signs generally, including linguistic representations, graphs, charts and diagrams, road sign symbols, animal communications, the "chemical signals" that regulate the function of glands, an…Read more
  • On Clear and Confused Ideas
    Cambridge Studies in Philosophy. 2001.
  • Afterword
    In Dan Ryder, Justine Kingsbury & Kenneth Williford (eds.), Millikan and her critics, Wiley. 2013.
  •  6
    On Meaning, Meaning and Meaning
    In Richard Schantz (ed.), Prospects for Meaning, Walter De Gruyter. pp. 85-106. 2012.
  •  7
    Truth Rules, Hoverflies, and the Kripke-Wittgenstein Paradox
    In Alexander Miller & Crispin Wright (eds.), Rule-Following and Meaning, Mcgill-queen's University Press. pp. 209-233. 2002.
  •  319
    What has Natural Information to Do with Intentional Representation?
    In D. Walsh (ed.), Evolution, Naturalism and Mind, Cambridge University Press. pp. 105-125. 2001.
    "According to informational semantics, if it's necessary that a creature can't distinguish Xs from Ys, it follows that the creature can't have a concept that applies to Xs but not Ys." (Jerry Fodor, The Elm and the Expert, p.32)
  •  32
    INTERVIEW: Gedacht wird in der Welt, nicht im Kopf
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 58 (6): 981-1000. 2010.
    This interview deals with the major themes in the work of Ruth Millikan. Her most fundamental idea is that the intentionality of inner and outer representations can be understood in analogy to biological functions. Another innovative feature is the view that thought and language stand parallel to each other. Thirdly, the basic ideas concerning the ontology and the epistemology of concepts are explained. Millikan aims at clarifying her position by contrasting it with Dretske, Fodor, Sellars, and …Read more
  •  37
    An evolutionist approach to language
    Philosophy Research Archives 5 286-319. 1979.
    I argue that looking for functions that explain the survival value of various language forms taken with their characteristic cooperative hearer responses, while looking also for functions that explain the survival value of the mental or neural equipments that learn to produce and to react to these language forms, is a reasonable and promising approach to the study of language and the philosophy of mind. The approach promises to help to unify the philosophy of language, showing clearly how the se…Read more
  •  75
    A Theory of Content and Other Essays (review)
    Philosophical Review 101 (4): 898-901. 1992.
  •  30
    A Theory of Content and Other Essays (review)
    Philosophical Review 101 (4): 898-901. 1992.
  •  181
    An Input Condition for Teleosemantics? Reply to Shea (and Godfrey-Smith)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (2): 436-455. 2007.
    In his essay "Consumers Need Information: Supplementing Teleosemantics with an Input Condition" (this issue) Nicholas Shea argues, with support from the work of Peter Godfrey-Smith (1996), that teleosemantics, as David Papinau and I have articulated it, cannot explain why "content attribution can be used to explain successful behavior." This failure is said to result from defining the intentional contents of representations by reference merely to historically normal conditions for success of the…Read more
  •  181
    Teleosemantics and the frogs
    Mind and Language 39 (1): 52-60. 2024.
    Some have thought that the plausibility of teleosemantics requires that it yield a determinate answer to the question of what the semantic “content” is of the “representation” triggered in the optic nerve of a frog that spots a fly. An outsize literature has resulted in which, unfortunately, a number of serious confusions and omissions that concern the way teleosemantics would have to work have appeared and been passed on uncorrected leaving a distorted and simplistic picture of the teleosemanti…Read more
  •  26
    “Teleosemantics and Pushmi-Pullyu Representations” (call it “TP-PR,” this journal 2014 79.3, 545–566) argues that core teleosemantics, particularly as defined in Millikan (Language, thought and other biological categories, MIT Press, Cambridge, 1984, J Philos 86(6):281–297, 1989, White queen psychology and other essays for Alice, MIT Press, Cambridge, 1993, Philosophical perspectives, Ridgeview Publishing, Alascadero, 1996, Varieties of meaning, MIT Press, Cambridge, 2004–2008), seems to imply t…Read more