-
631The Incentives Argument for Intellectual Property ProtectionIn Axel Gosseries, Alain Marciano & Alain Strowel (eds.), Intellectual Property and Theories of Justice, Basingstoke & N.y.: Palgrave Mcmillan. 2008.
-
593The Story of West Virginia Board of Education v. BarnetteIn Michael Dorf (ed.), Constitutional Law Stories, 2nd ed., Foundation Press. 2009.
-
495Wrongful Life, Procreative Responsibility, and the Significance of HarmLegal Theory 5 (2): 117-148. 1999.
-
486Intellectual PropertyIn Robert E. Goodin, Philip Pettit & Thomas Winfried Menko Pogge (eds.), A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy, Wiley-blackwell. 1996.Intellectual property theory grapples with intriguing questions about the political and personal significance of our mental labour and creativity, the metaphysics of art and expression, the justifications for private property, and conflicts between property and free expression rights. This chapter begins with an introduction to the nature of intellectual property, comparing intellectual property to physical property. It continues with an overview of some arguments for, and criticisms of, the leg…Read more
-
486Paternalism, Unconscionability Doctrine, and AccommodationPhilosophy and Public Affairs 29 (3): 205-250. 2000.The unconscionability doctrine in contract law enables a court to decline to enforce a contract whose terms are seriously one-sided, exploitative, or otherwise manifestly unfair. It is often criticized for being paternalist. The essay argues that the characterization of unconscionability doctrine as paternalist reflects common but misleading thought about paternalism and obscures more important issues about autonomy and social connection. The defense responds to another criticism: that unconscio…Read more
-
454Egalitarianism, Choice-Sensitivity, and AccommodationIn Philip Pettit (ed.), Reason and Value: Themes from the Work of Joseph Raz, Oxford Univ. Press. pp. 270--302. 2004.
-
447Promising, intimate relationships, and conventionalismPhilosophical Review 117 (4): 481-524. 2008.The power to promise is morally fundamental and does not, at its foundation, derive from moral principles that govern our use of conventions. Of course, many features of promising have conventional components—including which words, gestures, or conditions of silence create commitments. What is really at issue between conventionalists and nonconventionalists is whether the basic moral relation of promissory commitment derives from the moral principles that govern our use of social conventions. Ot…Read more
-
436Lockean Theories of Intellectual PropertyIn Stephen R. Munzer (ed.), New Essays in the Political Theory of Property, Cambridge Univ. Press. 2001.
-
419Race, Labor, and the Fair Equality of Opportunity PrincipleFordham Law Review 1643-1675 (2004) 72 (5): 1643-1675. 2004.
-
412What Is Really Wrong With Compelled Association?Northwestern University Law Review 99 (2): 839-888. 2005.
-
387The Story of West Virginia Board of Education v. BarnetteIn Michael Dorf (ed.), Constitutional Law Stories, 2nd ed., Foundation Press. 2009.
-
294Immoral, Conflicting, and Redundant PromisesIn R. Jay Wallace, Rahul Kumar & Samuel Freeman (eds.), Reasons and Recognition: Essays on the Philosophy of T. M. Scanlon, Oxford University Press. 2011.
-
270Harm and Its Moral SignificanceLegal Theory 18 (3): 357-398. 2012.Standard, familiar models portray harms and benefits as symmetrical. Usually, harm is portrayed as involving a worsening of one's situation, and benefits as involving an improvement. Yet morally, the aversion, prevention, and relief of harms seem, at least presumptively, to matter more than the provision, protection, and maintenance of comparable and often greater benefits. Standard models of harms and benefits have difficulty acknowledging this priority, much less explaining it. They also fail …Read more
-
247Reparations for U.S. Slavery and Justice over TimeIn David Wasserman & Melinda Roberts (eds.), Harming Future Persons: Ethics, Genetics and the Nonidentity Problem, Springer. 2009.
-
145Speech Matters: On Lying, Morality, and the LawPrinceton University Press. 2014.To understand one another as individuals and to fulfill the moral duties that require such understanding, we must communicate with each other. We must also maintain protected channels that render reliable communication possible, a demand that, Seana Shiffrin argues, yields a prohibition against lying and requires protection for free speech. This book makes a distinctive philosophical argument for the wrong of the lie and provides an original account of its difference from the wrong of deception.…Read more
-
70I—Learning about Deception from LawyersAristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 93 (1): 69-90. 2019.Legal domains concerned with deception often recognize and regulate cases of negligent deception. The philosophical discussion of deception should follow suit, shifting from an exclusive focus on deception-as-wrongful-manipulation to a broader panorama that includes negligent deception and contemplates cases in which negligent deception may be wrong even when intentional deception about the same information may be permissible. Interesting philosophical questions then arise about what distinguish…Read more
-
62Chapter Three. A Thinker-Based Approach to Freedom of SpeechIn Speech Matters: On Lying, Morality, and the Law, Princeton University Press. pp. 79-115. 2014.
-
61Chapter One. Lies and the Murderer Next DoorIn Speech Matters: On Lying, Morality, and the Law, Princeton University Press. pp. 5-46. 2014.
-
56The Norton Introduction to Philosophy (edited book)W. W. Norton. 2015.Edited by a team of four leading philosophers, The Norton Introduction to Philosophy introduces students to contemporary perspectives on major philosophical issues and questions. This text features an impressive array of readings, including 25 specially-commissioned essays by prominent philosophers. A student-friendly presentation, a handy format, and a low price make The Norton Introduction to Philosophy as accessible and affordable as it is up-to-date.
-
52Back-door Lies and Promising under CoercionMind. forthcoming.I’m grateful to Professors Langton and Owens for their probing comments and to Mind for providing the occasion for this exchange. Both Langton and Owens helpfully push me to tackle interesting problems that I did not wrestle with in the book. I am game to try to answer them, but some of my responses are tentative and roughly hewn, offered more in the spirit of exploratory conversation than firm conviction.
-
47Caution about character ideals and capital punishment: A reply to SorellCriminal Justice Ethics 21 (2): 35-39. 2002.
Areas of Specialization
Normative Ethics |
Philosophy of Law |
Social and Political Philosophy |
Areas of Interest
Epistemology |
Applied Ethics |
Meta-Ethics |
Philosophy of Law |
Social and Political Philosophy |