•  5466
    Désirs naturels et artificiels chez Diogène et Épicure
    In Daoust Marc-Kevin (ed.), Le désir et la philosophie, Les Cahiers D'ithaque. pp. 147. 2015.
    This article contrasts Epicurus's and Diogenes the Cynic's respective views on acceptable desires. I emphasize their appeals to nature to legitimize or de-legitimize certain types of desires.
  •  795
    Comme de nombreux penseurs antiques avant et après eux et contrairement à Socrate, Calliclès et Diogène ont déclaré avoir fondé leur éthique sur l’observation de la nature. Et pourtant, les deux discours normatifs qui sont tirés d’une nature que l’on pourrait a priori croire être la même sont on ne peut plus opposés. Calliclès croit que l’homme est appelé à dominer autrui ; Diogène pense plutôt qu’il doit se dominer lui-même ; le premier est un hédoniste débridé, le second croit que le bonheur n…Read more
  •  561
    Prostitution: You Can’t Have Your Cake and Sell It
    Journal of Practical Ethics 5 (2): 77-84. 2017.
    I offer an unorthodox argument for the thesis that prostitution is not just a normal job. It has the advantage of being compatible with the claim that humans should have full authority over their sexual life. In fact, it is ultimately the emphasis on this authority that leads the thesis that prostitution is a normal job to collapse. Here is the argument: merchants cannot (both legally and morally) discriminate whom they transact with on the basis of factors like the ethnicity or the religion of …Read more
  •  268
    Recensement: Hyman - Action, Knowledge and Will (review)
    Philosophiques 42 (2): 435-440. 2015.
    Ce compte-rendu résume les quatre dimensions de la philosophie de l’ action défendue dans Action, Knowledge and Will : physique, éthique, psychologique et intellectuel. Cela dit, les deux contributions principales du livre recensé relèvent de liens entre les différentes dimensions de l’ action. Il s’agit d’une distinction et d’une connexion. Premièrement, Hyman croit qu’il faut distinguer la dimension éthique et la dimension physique de l’ action. Plus précisément, il pense que le concept de vol…Read more
  •  231
    No one is responsible for their conduct because free will is an illusion, say some skeptics. Even when it seems that we have several options, we only have one. Hence, says the free will skeptic, we should reform our practices which involve responsibility attributions, such as punishment and blame. How seriously should we take this doctrine? Is it one that we could live by? One thorn in the side of the skeptic concerns deliberation. When we deliberate about what to do—what film to go see, whom to…Read more
  •  147
    Relever le défi déterministe une défense à la fois
    Chroniques Universitaires. forthcoming.
    In this leçon inaugurale (inaugural lecture) at the University of Neuchâtel, I explain how we can tackle the problem of determinism by asking whether it would give us a justification, an excuse, or an exemption. This strategy builds on Peter Strawson's in Freedom and Resentment, but completes it by (1) proposing a theory of excuses ; (2) proposing that lacking alternatives might give a weak justification--i.e. it might exclude wrongdoing. This forces us to make the best of two philosophical trad…Read more
  •  115
    Sceptical Deliberations
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 101 (3): 383-408. 2020.
    Suppose I am a leeway sceptic: I think that, whenever I face a choice between two courses of action, I lack true alternatives. Can my practical deliberation be rational? Call this the Deliberation Question. This paper has three aims in tackling it. Its constructive aim is to provide a unified account of practical deliberation. Its corrective aim is to amend the way that philosophers have recently framed the Deliberation Question. Finally, its disputative aim is to argue that leeway sceptics cann…Read more
  •  77
    Self-Defeating Beliefs and Misleading Reasons
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 27 (1): 57-72. 2019.
    We have no reason to believe that reasons do not exist. Contra Bart Streumer’s recent proposal, this has nothing to do with our incapacity to believe this error theory. Rather, it is because if we know that if a proposition is true, we have no reason to believe it, then we have no reason to believe this proposition. From a different angle: if we know that we have at best misleading reasons to believe a proposition, then we have no reason to believe it. This has two consequences. Firstly, coming …Read more
  •  68
    Is Free Will Scepticism Self-Defeating?
    European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 15 (2): 55-78. 2019.
    Free will sceptics deny the existence of free will, that is the command or control necessary for moral responsibility. Epicureans allege that this denial is somehow self-defeating. To interpret the Epicurean allegation charitably, we must first realise that it is propositional attitudes like beliefs and not propositions themselves which can be self-defeating. So, believing in free will scepticism might be self- defeating. The charge becomes more plausible because, as Epicurus insightfully recogn…Read more
  •  56
    Le solidarisme de Léon Bourgeois constitue une tentative convaincante de surmonter l’opposition traditionnelle entre libertés individuelles et justice sociale. Bourgeois tente de relever ce défi en faisant appel aux nouvelles découvertes scientifiques en sociologie comme en biologie. En bref, l’observation de la nature nous montrerait que les humains sont en rapport de solidarité les uns avec les autres. De ce fait, on pourrait tirer un devoir de solidarité que l’État serait à même d’imposer aux…Read more
  •  55
    Excuses and Alternatives
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 51 (1): 1-16. 2021.
    A version of the principle of alternate possibilities claims that one is only blameworthy for actions which one was able to avoid. Much of the discussion about PAP concerns Frankfurt’s counterexamples to it. After fifty years of refined debates, progress might seem hopeless. Yet, we can make headway by asking: “what’s our reason for believing PAP?” The best answer is this: lacking eligible alternatives—alternatives whose cost is not too high to reasonably opt for—is a good excuse. Yet, this prin…Read more
  •  46
    THE CONTOURS OF FREE WILL SCEPTICISM
    Dissertation, Oxford University. 2019.
    Free will sceptics claim that we lack free will, i.e. the command or control of our conduct that is required for moral responsibility. There are different conceptions of free will: it is sometimes understood as having the ability to choose between real options or alternatives; and sometimes as being the original or true source of our own conduct. Whether conceived in the first or in the second way, free will is subject to strong sceptical arguments. However, free will sceptics face a difficulty:…Read more
  •  39
    Knowing About Responsibility
    American Philosophical Quarterly 58 (3): 201-216. 2021.
    Here is a skeptical trilemma. We know that we are responsible. We do not know that determinism is false. Yet, if we do not know that determinism is false, we do not know that we are responsible. If we want to avoid the skeptical conclusion of rejecting the first claim, we ought to reject the third. It does not follow that compatibilism is true. But it follows that libertarianism, the view that we are responsible even though responsibility requires indeterminism, is unknowable, at least for now. …Read more
  •  34
    Ceci est un recensement du livre de John Hyman 'Action, Knowledge, and the Will'. This is a book review (in French) of John Hyman's book 'Action, Knowledge, and the Will'.
  •  26
    SIMON-PIERRE CHEVARIE-COSSETTE
  •  22
    Simon-Pierre Chevarie-Cossette
  •  15
    Deux formes de naturalisme antique : la nature comme fondement d’éthiques contradictoires
    In Eliot Litalien, Cléa Bénoliel, Simon-Pierre Chevarie-Cossette, Emmannuelle Gauthier-Lamer, Hutter Thiago, Mekhaël Thomas & Sagnières Louis (eds.), Peut-on tirer une éthique de l'observation de la nature?, Les Cahiers D'ithaque. 2013.
    Diogène de Sinope et Calliclès affirment tirer leurs éthiques de l'observation de la nature. En cela, ils s'opposent explicitement à Socrate. Mais leur position est-elle une véritable forme de naturalisme ou un simple usage métaphorique? Ce texte défend la première option, après avoir montré que malgré leur ressemblance métaéthique, ces deux éthiques normatives sont radicalement opposées.
  •  13
    Introduction
    In Éliot Litalien, Cléa Bénoliel, Simon-Pierre Chevarie-Cossette, Emmanuelle Gauthier-Lamer, Thiago Hutter, Thomas Mekhaël & Louis Sagnières (eds.), Peut-on tirer une éthique de l'observation de la nature?, Les Cahiers D'ithaque. pp. 1-5. 2013.
    Ce recueil réunit des articles qui s'interrogent, depuis un ensemble de perspectives philosophiques des plus diverses, sur le rapport entre nature et éthique.