•  10
    The Mechaniziation of Natural Philosophy (edited book)
    Springer. 2012.
    Voir : https://philosophie.ens.fr/Dir-avec-D-Garber-The-Mechanisation-of-Natural-Philosophy.html.
  •  5
    La mathématisation comme problème (edited book)
    with Hugues Chabot
    Édiitons des Archives contemporaines. 2011.
    L'histoire des sciences suffit à réfuter la thèse de la mathématisation impossible, selon laquelle la mathématisation procéderait d'un formalisme abstrait manquant les choses mêmes ou la spécificité d'un domaine d'objets. Cette histoire montre en effet qu'on n'a pas cessé de mathématiser des choses dont il avait été longtemps dit qu'elles devaient, étant donné leur nature, éternellement résister à la mathématisation. À la thèse de la mathématisation impossible, il est dès lors tentant d'opposer …Read more
  • Louis Couturat (1868-1914) (edited book)
    with Michel Fichant
    Classiques Garnier. 2017.
  •  4
    Un colloque international « L'automate: modèle, machine, merveille »
    with Aurélia Gaillard, Jean-Yves Goffi, and Bernard Roukhomovsky
    Revue de Synthèse 130 (1): 217-219. 2009.
  •  22
    Présentation
    with Irène Passeron
    Revue de Synthèse 122 (2-4): 271-286. 2001.
  •  39
    Comptes rendus
    with Jean-Marc Drouin, Patrick Gautier Dalché, Fabien Chareix, Charles Lenay, Monique Cottret, Bernard Vandewalle, François Laplanche, Françoise Waquet, Agnès Spiquel, Ariane Poulantzas, Olivier Martin, Ilana Löwy, Isabelle Brian, Michel Cassan, Jean-Marc Rohrbasser, Jean-Michel Vienne, Marc Renneville, Bernard Lahire, Mikhaäl Xifaras, Bertrand Binoche, Stéphane Haber, Jean-François Pradeau, Noël Bonneuil, and Marie Jaisson
    Revue de Synthèse 118 (4): 551-613. 1997.
  •  22
    Histoire de la philosophie
    with Laurence Devillairs, Pascal Séverac, Gabrielle Radica, Luc Ruiz, Mai Lequan, Jean-François Goubet, Jean-Marc Rohrbasser, and Sophie Nordmann
    Revue de Synthèse 122 (1): 207-232. 2001.
  •  28
    Histoire intellectuelle du xviiie siècle
    with Mariana Saad, Anne Lagny, Bruno Neveu, Françoise Waquet, and Elsa Dorlin
    Revue de Synthèse 122 (2-4): 688-705. 2001.
  •  374
    Le scepticisme et les hypothèses de la physique
    Revue de Synthèse 119 (2-3): 211-255. 1998.
    The History of scepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza is often called upon to support three theses: first, that Descartes had a dogmatic notion of systematic knowledge, and therefore of physics; second, that the hypothetical epistemology of physics which spread during the xviith century was the result of a general sceptical crisis; third, that this epistemology was more successful in England than in France. I reject these three theses: I point first to the tension in Descartes’ works between the ide…Read more
  •  237
    Les lois de la nature à l''ge classique la question terminologique
    Revue de Synthèse 122 (2-4): 531-576. 2001.
    Four propositions relative to the laws of nature in the classical period must be noted. 1. Certain regularities in phenomena had been discovered. 2. A concept of law had emerged. 3. Classical science is characterized by the introduction of the notion of the legality of nature. 4. New uses of the word «law» had appeared in scientific texts. This article is devoted to the analysis of only this last proposition, that is to say to a terminological problem. First we will describe the semantic uses of…Read more
  •  5
    Logique et méthode au xviie siècle
    Les Cahiers Philosophiques de Strasbourg 32 21-45. 2012.
    I begin by briefly recalling two facts of seventeenth century intellectual history: not only is a fourth part devoted to method added to the three parts traditionally contained in logic treatises, but in a number of texts the terms "logic" and "method" are blurred. I then give an explanation of these two facts with the following ideas: 1/ Since the criticism of Aristotelian sciences at the beginning of the seventeenth century was in particular focused on logic, the question was asked as to what …Read more
  •  19
    Roger Ariew's new book, Descartes and the First Cartesians, will not be a methodological surprise for those who already read his previous work, Descartes and the Last Scholastics, as well as its expanded version, Descartes Among the Scholastics. Right at the beginning of DAS, Ariew justified the title of this book in the following way: A philosophical system cannot be studied adequately apart from the intellectual context in which it is situated. Philosophers do not usually utter propositions in…Read more
  •  11
    During the seventeenth century there were different ways of opposing the new mechanical philosophy and the old Aristotelian philosophy. Remarkably enough, one of this way succeeded in becoming stable beyond the moment of its formulation, one according to which Descartes would be the benchmark by which the works of other natural philosophers of the seventeenth century fall either on the side of the old or the new. I consequently examine the French debate where this representation emerges, a debat…Read more
  •  6
    A Deflationist Solution to the Problem of Forces
    In Delphine Antoine-Mahut & Sophie Roux (eds.), Physics and Metaphysics in Descartes and in His Reception, Routledge. pp. 141-159. 2018.
    The ontological status of forces and their causal role in Descartes’ physical world is debated among Descartes scholars. The question of forces is embedded in another more general question, namely to determine which causal activity should be attributed to God, and which causal activity should be attributed to physical bodies. Three distinct positions were attributed to Descartes: 1. he was an occasionalist and he attributed no causal power to forces, 2. he was a pure conservationist and he conce…Read more
  •  5
    The mechanical (or corpuscular philosophy) has been well-established as a historiographical category for some years now. While it certainly began as an actor’s category, it has slipped into being something else, a kind of broad catch-all category that is taken to include most of those who opposed the Aristotelian philosophy of the schools throughout the entire seventeenth century, part of a broad master narrative about the demise of the scholastic Aristotelian philosophy of the schools and the r…Read more
  •  21
    The mechanical philosophy that emerged during the Scientific Revolution can be characterised as a reductionism according to which all physical phenomena are to be explained in terms of corpuscles of different sizes, shapes, and motions. It provided early modern natural philosophers with a unified view of nature that contrasted primarily with the Aristotelian view of nature, but also with other naturalist, hermetic, mystic, occultist, Paracelsian, and chymical accounts. Indeed, early modern natur…Read more
  •  15
    In November 1664, a comet appeared in the European skies; by early March 1665, it had disappeared, but, at this very moment, another comet appeared, which stayed among the stars until mid-April. Observations of these two comets were made all over Europe, and even beyond. Although most secondary literature dedicated to these two comets has been focused on England and Italy, France was not to be outdone in terms of observations, small talk and publications. In this paper, I would like to use the b…Read more
  •  8
    Leaving aside here the question of the author of the Essai de logique, I show that, if Mariotte insisted on the specificity of physics, he also sought a certain inspiration in mathematics as to the way in which to lay out the propositions in a proof. To do so, I start off from the ontological distinction made in the Essai among three types of possibles; next we will show that the three types of propositions correspond to three types of knowledge, and, correlatively, that the main problem of phys…Read more
  •  10
    From the Mechanical Philosophy to Early Modern Mechanisms
    In Stuart Glennan & Phyllis McKay Illari (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Mechanisms and Mechanical Philosophy, Routledge. pp. 26-45. 2017.
    Early modern natural philosophers put forward the ontological program that was called "mechanical philosophy" and they gave mechanical explanations for all kinds of phenomena, such as gravity, magnetism, the colors of the rainbow, the circulation of the blood, the motion of the heart and the development of animals. For a generation of historians, the mechanical philosophy was regarded as the main alternative to Aristotelian orthodoxy during the so-called Scientific Revolution and mechanical expl…Read more
  •  5
    Physics and metaphysics in Descartes and in his reception (edited book)
    with Delphine Kolesnik-Antoine
    Routledge, Taylor and Francis Group. 2018.
    This volume explores the relationship between physics and metaphysics in Descartes’ philosophy. According to the standard account, Descartes modified the objects of metaphysics and physics and inverted the order in which these two disciplines were traditionally studied. This book challenges the standard account in which Descartes prioritizes metaphysics over physics. It does so by taking into consideration the historical reception of Descartes and the ways in which Descartes himself reacted to t…Read more
  • The condemnations of Cartesian natural philosophy under Louis XIV (1661-91)
    In Steven Nadler, Tad M. Schmaltz & Delphine Antoine-Mahut (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Descartes and Cartesianism, Oxford University Press. 2019.
  •  22
    Résumé Cet article esquisse une généalogie du privilège que le terme concept a acquis en français par rapport à notion et à idée en se fondant non seulement sur les ouvrages des philosophes, mais sur des dictionnaires de langue philosophique. Il comprend quatre parties chronologiques. Après avoir étudié l’introduction des termes concept, notion, idée dans la langue philosophique, la première partie répertorie leurs usages dans les dictionnaires scolastiques du SVIIe siècle. La deuxième montre qu…Read more
  •  7
    This volume explores the relationship between physics and metaphysics in Descartes' philosophy. According to the standard account, Descartes modified the objects of metaphysics and physics and inverted the order in which these two disciplines were traditionally studied. This book challenges the standard account in which Descartes prioritizes metaphysics over physics. It does so by taking into consideration the historical reception of Descartes and the ways in which Descartes himself reacted to t…Read more
  •  77
    The enigma of the inclined plane from Heron to Galileo
    with Egidio Festa
    In W. R. Laird & S. Roux (eds.), Mechanics and Natural Philosophy Before the Scientific Revolution, . pp. 195-222. 2008.
    Festa, E., Roux, S. (2008). The Enigma of the Inclined Plane from Heron to Galileo. In: Laird, W.R., Roux, S. (eds) Mechanics and Natural Philosophy Before the Scientific Revolution. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 254. Springer, Dordrecht.
  •  35
    Meyerson et les mathématiques
    Corpus: Revue de philosophie 58 3-38. 2010.
    Mes réflexions sur Meyerson et les mathématiques ont pour origine trois questions : 1) Une idée reçue est que, des trois synthèses de Meyerson -- Identité et réalité, De l'explication dans les sciences et Du cheminement de la pensée -- , seule la dernière analyse les mathématiques, en elles-mêmes aussi bien que dans leurs rapports avec la pensée. La première question est donc de déterminer si cette idée reçue est correcte ou bien si l'on peut trouver dans les deux autres ouvrages des indications…Read more
  •  13
    Forms of Mathematization (14th -17th Centuries)
    Early Science and Medicine 15 (4-5): 319-337. 2010.
    According to a grand narrative that long ago ceased to be told, there was a seventeenth century Scientific Revolution, during which a few heroes conquered nature thanks to mathematics. This grand narrative began with the exhibition of quantitative laws that these heroes, Galileo and Newton for example, had disclosed: the law of falling bodies, according to which the speed of a falling body is proportional to the square of the time that has elapsed since the beginning of its fall; the law of grav…Read more