Saint Louis University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1977
College Station, Texas, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
17th/18th Century Philosophy
  •  20
    Descartes on Immortality and Animals
    The European Legacy 29 (2): 184-198. 2023.
    For Descartes, our minds are not natural causes because they are not themselves objects; rather, they are the activities that identify objects. In short, they are our challenges to the natural order of things, both in how we adapt to novel situations (as exhibited in what has been called the “rational action test”) and in how we respond in unexpected yet appropriate ways to linguistic cues (in the “language test”). Because these tests reveal ways in which our minds (as “pure,” creative, willful,…Read more
  •  17
    George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy
    Oxford University Press. 2021.
    This book is a study of the philosophy of the early 18th century Irish philosopher George Berkeley in the intellectual context of his times, with a particular focus on how, for Berkeley, mind is related to its ideas. It does not assume that thinkers like Descartes, Malebranche, or Locke define for Berkeley the context in which he develops his own thought. Instead, he indicates how Berkeley draws on a tradition that informed his early training and that challenges much of the early modern thought …Read more
  •  59
    Berkeley on God
    In Samuel C. Rickless (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Berkeley, Oxford University Press. pp. 177-93. 2022.
    Berkeley’s appeal to a posteriori arguments for God’s existence supports belief only in a God who is finite. But by appealing to an a priori argument for God’s existence, Berkeley emphasizes God’s infinity. In this latter argument, God is not the efficient cause of particular finite things in the world, for such an explanation does not provide a justification or rationale for why the totality of finite things would exist in the first place. Instead, God is understood as the creator of the total …Read more
  •  9
    The Semiotic Ontology of Jonathan Edwards
    Modern Schoolman 71 (4): 285-304. 1994.
  •  6
    M. Hobbes and America: Exploring the Constitutional Foundations (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 36 (3): 698-699. 1983.
    Though some of the critical reviews of Frank M. Coleman's Hobbes and America have alluded to the affinities of his work to that of Strauss, Macpherson, Laslett, and Oakeshott, most have ignored Coleman's specifically philosophic treatment of Hobbes as the foundational thinker most responsive to political realities which emerge in the seventeenth century and still characterize American politics. Coleman's purpose is to demonstrate how the operative American constitutional philosophy can be recogn…Read more
  •  34
    Substance and Person: Berkeley on Descartes and Locke
    Ruch Filozoficzny 74 (4): 7. 2018.
    In his post-1720 works, Berkeley focuses his comments about Descartes on mechanism and about Locke on general abstract ideas. He warns against using metaphysical principles to explain observed regularities, and he extends his account to include spiritual substances (including God). Indeed, by calling a substance a spirit, he emphasizes how a person is simply the will that ideas be differentiated and associated in a certain way, not some <i>thing</i> that engages in differentiation. In this sense…Read more
  •  48
    Berkeley's Non-Cartesian Notion of Spiritual Substance
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (4): 659-682. 2018.
    As central as the notion of mind is for Berkeley, it is not surprising that what he means by mind stirs debate. At issue are questions about not only what kind of thing a mind is but also how we can know it. This convergence of ontological and epistemological interests in discussing mind has led some commentators to argue that Berkeley's appeal to the Cartesian vocabulary of 'spiritual substance' signals his appropriation of elements of Descartes's theory of mind. But in his account of spiritual…Read more
  •  753
    Berkeley on God's Knowledge of Pain
    In Stefan Storrie (ed.), Berkeley's Three Dialogues: New Essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 136-145. 2018.
    Since nothing about God is passive, and the perception of pain is inherently passive, then it seems that God does not know what it is like to experience pain. Nor would he be able to cause us to experience pain, for his experience would then be a sensation (which would require God to have senses, which he does not). My suggestion is that Berkeley avoids this situation by describing how God knows about pain “among other things” (i.e. as something whose identity is intelligible in terms of the int…Read more
  •  38
    Transforming the Hermeneutic Context (review)
    New Vico Studies 8 (n/a): 127-129. 1990.
  •  12
    The Ramist Context of Berkeley's Philosophy
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (3): 487-505. 2001.
  • The Nature of Light in Descartes' Physics
    Philosophical Forum 7 (3): 323. 1976.
  •  22
    Berkeley: Philosophical Writings, ed. Desmond M. Clarke (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (7). 2009.
  •  66
    Civility and sociability: Hobbes on man and citizen
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 18 (2): 209-215. 1980.
  •  540
    Berkeley's Doctrine of Mind and the “Black List Hypothesis”: A Dialogue
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (1): 24-41. 2013.
    Clues about what Berkeley was planning to say about mind in his now-lost second volume of the Principles seem to abound in his Notebooks. However, commentators have been reluctant to use his unpublished entries to explicate his remarks about spiritual substances in the Principles and Dialogues for three reasons. First, it has proven difficult to reconcile the seemingly Humean bundle theory of the self in the Notebooks with Berkeley's published characterization of spirits as “active beings or pri…Read more
  •  66
    Preparations for a Research Paper in Philosophy
    Teaching Philosophy 3 (2): 185-188. 1979.
  • Ramist Dialectic in Leibniz's Early Thought
    In Mark Kulstad, Mogens Laerke & David Snyder (eds.), The Philosophy of the Young Leibniz, Steiner Verlag. pp. 59-66. 2009.
  •  13
    Myth and modern philosophy
    Temple University Press. 1990.
    A study of the historiographic significance and use of mythic or fabular thinking in Bacon, Descartes, Mandeville, Vico, Herder, and others.
  •  23
    An examination of Edwards’ ontology and his ideas on creation, God, sin, freedom, virtue, and beauty.
  •  16
    Hobbes and America (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 36 (3): 698-700. 1983.
  •  18
    Seventeenth-Century Scholastic Treatments of Time
    Journal of the History of Ideas 42 (4): 587-606. 1981.
  •  42
    Descartes on Myth and Ingenuity / Ingenium
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 23 (2): 157-170. 1985.
  •  534
    Berkeley, Suárez, and the Esse-Existere Distinction
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 74 (4): 621-636. 2000.
    For Berkeley, a thing's existence 'esse' is nothing more than its being perceived 'as that thing'. It makes no sense to ask (with Samuel Johnson) about the 'esse' of the mind or the specific act of perception, for that would be like asking what it means for existence to exist. Berkeley's "existere is percipi or percipere" (NB 429) thus carefully adopts the scholastic distinction between 'esse' and 'existere' ignored by Locke and others committed to a substantialist notion of mind. Following the …Read more
  •  42
    Wilhelm Dilthey (review)
    New Vico Studies 4 (n/a): 175-178. 1986.
  •  50
    Berkeley's 'Alciphron': English Text and Essays in Interpretation (review)
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (3). 2011.
  •  73
    Metaphor in the Historiography of Philosophy
    Clio: A Journal of Literature, History, and the Philosophy of History 15 (2): 191-210. 1986.
  •  63
    Vico's historicism and the ontology of arguments
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (3): 431-446. 1995.
    Vico's historicist claims (1) that different ages are intelligible only in their own terms and (2) that the certainty and authority of history depend on its narrative formulation seem at odds with his doctrines of ideal eternal history and divine providence. He resolves these issues, however, in his treatment of ideal eternal history by using the distinction between the certain and the true to show how rhetorical expression generates meaning in and as history. Specifically, by appealing to an on…Read more
  •  595
    Edwards' Occasionalism
    In Don Schweitzer (ed.), Jonathan Edwards as Contemporary, Peter Lang. pp. 1-14. 2010.
    Instead of focusing on the Malebranche-Edwards connection regarding occasionalism as if minds are distinct from the ideas they have, I focus on how finite minds are particular expressions of God's will that there be the distinctions by which ideas are identified and differentiated. This avoids problems, created in the accounts of Fiering, Lee, and especially Crisp, about the inherently idealist character of Edwards' occasionalism.