Saint Louis University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1977
College Station, Texas, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
17th/18th Century Philosophy
  •  22
    Descartes on Immortality and Animals
    The European Legacy 29 (2): 184-198. 2023.
    For Descartes, our minds are not natural causes because they are not themselves objects; rather, they are the activities that identify objects. In short, they are our challenges to the natural order of things, both in how we adapt to novel situations (as exhibited in what has been called the “rational action test”) and in how we respond in unexpected yet appropriate ways to linguistic cues (in the “language test”). Because these tests reveal ways in which our minds (as “pure,” creative, willful,…Read more
  •  17
    George Berkeley and Early Modern Philosophy
    Oxford University Press. 2021.
    This book is a study of the philosophy of the early 18th century Irish philosopher George Berkeley in the intellectual context of his times, with a particular focus on how, for Berkeley, mind is related to its ideas. It does not assume that thinkers like Descartes, Malebranche, or Locke define for Berkeley the context in which he develops his own thought. Instead, he indicates how Berkeley draws on a tradition that informed his early training and that challenges much of the early modern thought …Read more
  •  60
    Berkeley on God
    In Samuel C. Rickless (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Berkeley, Oxford University Press. pp. 177-93. 2022.
    Berkeley’s appeal to a posteriori arguments for God’s existence supports belief only in a God who is finite. But by appealing to an a priori argument for God’s existence, Berkeley emphasizes God’s infinity. In this latter argument, God is not the efficient cause of particular finite things in the world, for such an explanation does not provide a justification or rationale for why the totality of finite things would exist in the first place. Instead, God is understood as the creator of the total …Read more
  •  9
    The Semiotic Ontology of Jonathan Edwards
    Modern Schoolman 71 (4): 285-304. 1994.
  •  6
    M. Hobbes and America: Exploring the Constitutional Foundations (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 36 (3): 698-699. 1983.
    Though some of the critical reviews of Frank M. Coleman's Hobbes and America have alluded to the affinities of his work to that of Strauss, Macpherson, Laslett, and Oakeshott, most have ignored Coleman's specifically philosophic treatment of Hobbes as the foundational thinker most responsive to political realities which emerge in the seventeenth century and still characterize American politics. Coleman's purpose is to demonstrate how the operative American constitutional philosophy can be recogn…Read more
  •  34
    Substance and Person: Berkeley on Descartes and Locke
    Ruch Filozoficzny 74 (4): 7. 2018.
    In his post-1720 works, Berkeley focuses his comments about Descartes on mechanism and about Locke on general abstract ideas. He warns against using metaphysical principles to explain observed regularities, and he extends his account to include spiritual substances (including God). Indeed, by calling a substance a spirit, he emphasizes how a person is simply the will that ideas be differentiated and associated in a certain way, not some <i>thing</i> that engages in differentiation. In this sense…Read more
  •  49
    Berkeley's Non-Cartesian Notion of Spiritual Substance
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (4): 659-682. 2018.
    As central as the notion of mind is for Berkeley, it is not surprising that what he means by mind stirs debate. At issue are questions about not only what kind of thing a mind is but also how we can know it. This convergence of ontological and epistemological interests in discussing mind has led some commentators to argue that Berkeley's appeal to the Cartesian vocabulary of 'spiritual substance' signals his appropriation of elements of Descartes's theory of mind. But in his account of spiritual…Read more
  •  756
    Berkeley on God's Knowledge of Pain
    In Stefan Storrie (ed.), Berkeley's Three Dialogues: New Essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 136-145. 2018.
    Since nothing about God is passive, and the perception of pain is inherently passive, then it seems that God does not know what it is like to experience pain. Nor would he be able to cause us to experience pain, for his experience would then be a sensation (which would require God to have senses, which he does not). My suggestion is that Berkeley avoids this situation by describing how God knows about pain “among other things” (i.e. as something whose identity is intelligible in terms of the int…Read more
  •  38
    Transforming the Hermeneutic Context (review)
    New Vico Studies 8 (n/a): 127-129. 1990.
  •  12
    The Ramist Context of Berkeley's Philosophy
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (3): 487-505. 2001.
  •  38
    Doubts and Doubting in Descartes
    Modern Schoolman 56 (1): 57-65. 1978.
  •  426
    Berkeley's Rejection of Divine Analogy
    Science Et Esprit 63 (2): 149-161. 2011.
    Berkeley argues that claims about divine predication (e.g., God is wise or exists) should be understood literally rather than analogically, because like all spirits (i.e., causes), God is intelligible only in terms of the extent of his effects. By focusing on the harmony and order of nature, Berkeley thus unites his view of God with his doctrines of mind, force, grace, and power, and avoids challenges to religious claims that are raised by appeals to analogy. The essay concludes by showing how a…Read more
  •  28
    Paramodern Strategies of Philosophical Historiography
    Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 1 (1): 41-63. 1993.
  •  28
    A philosophical theory of literary continuity and change
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 18 (3): 275-280. 1980.
  •  35
    Montréal Conference Summaries
    with Sébastien Charles
    Berkeley Studies 23 54-57. 2012.
    In June of 2012 scholars from Europe and North America met in Montreal to commemorate the 300th anniversary of the publication of George Berkeley's *Passive Obedience*. In this article Stephen Daniel summarizes the English presentations, and Sébastien Charles summarizes the French presentations, on how Berkeley invokes naturalistic themes in developing a moral theory while still allowing a role for God.
  •  33
    The Semiotic Ontology of Jonathan Edwards
    Modern Schoolman 71 (4): 285-304. 1994.
    Jonathan Edwards' marginalization in modern philosophy stems from his refusal to endorse the predicational logic and substantialist ontology of the rationalist-empiricist debate. Instead, he appeals to a communicative, semiotic logic of propositions grounded in Stoic thought and thematized by Peter Ramus and his Puritan followers. That alternative logic displays an "ontology of supposition" that guarantees God's existence, justifies typological, magical, and even astrological inferences, undermi…Read more
  •  8
    Incoming Editor’s Note
    Berkeley Studies 17 3. 2006.
    A quick introduction to my becoming the editor of *Berkeley Studies* in 2006.
  • The Nature of Light in Descartes' Physics
    Philosophical Forum 7 (3): 323. 1976.
  •  66
    Civility and sociability: Hobbes on man and citizen
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 18 (2): 209-215. 1980.
  •  22
    Berkeley: Philosophical Writings, ed. Desmond M. Clarke (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (7). 2009.
  •  544
    Berkeley's Doctrine of Mind and the “Black List Hypothesis”: A Dialogue
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 51 (1): 24-41. 2013.
    Clues about what Berkeley was planning to say about mind in his now-lost second volume of the Principles seem to abound in his Notebooks. However, commentators have been reluctant to use his unpublished entries to explicate his remarks about spiritual substances in the Principles and Dialogues for three reasons. First, it has proven difficult to reconcile the seemingly Humean bundle theory of the self in the Notebooks with Berkeley's published characterization of spirits as “active beings or pri…Read more
  •  66
    Preparations for a Research Paper in Philosophy
    Teaching Philosophy 3 (2): 185-188. 1979.
  • Ramist Dialectic in Leibniz's Early Thought
    In Mark Kulstad, Mogens Laerke & David Snyder (eds.), The philosophy of the young Leibniz, Steiner. pp. 59-66. 2009.
  •  14
    Myth and modern philosophy
    Temple University Press. 1990.
    A study of the historiographic significance and use of mythic or fabular thinking in Bacon, Descartes, Mandeville, Vico, Herder, and others.
  •  16
    Hobbes and America (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 36 (3): 698-700. 1983.