•  7
    Skeptical Theism, CORNEA, and Common Sense Epistemology
    In Justin P. McBrayer & Daniel Howard‐Snyder (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to the Problem of Evil, Wiley. 2013.
    The problem of evil is best understood as an instance of what I call “the problem of defeated expectations.” These problems arise for theism when the world we experience does not conform to what we would expect to find in a world created and sustained by a being who is omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent. In this chapter, I explore skeptical theism, which is an approach to the evidential problem of evil that argues that, at least with respect to certain kinds of evils we find, we simply s…Read more
  •  13
    Selected papers in honor of William P. Alston (edited book)
    with Michael R. DePaul and William P. Alston
    Philosophy Documentation Center. 2016.
    William P. Alston was the founding editor of the Philosophy Research Archives and a president of the American Philosophical Association. This special volume was prepared in honor and recognition of Alston's many contributions to philosophy as author, editor, teacher, and mentor. Publication of this volume was made possible by his colleagues and the philosophy department at Syracuse University.
  • Defending Divine Freedom
    Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion 1 168-195. 2008.
  •  5
    Warrant: The Current DebateWarrant and Proper Function (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 48 (4): 925-925. 1995.
    Whereas the first book is designed to demonstrate the inadequacy of other accounts, the second volume is supposed to tell us the sober truth about warrant. In a nutshell, Plantinga's theory is that a belief has warrant to the extent that it is produced by a cognitive process that is truth-aimed, functioning properly, operating in an appropriate environment, and reliable. Furthermore, for any two warranted beliefs, the belief which is held most strongly is the most warranted. Plantinga is aware t…Read more
  •  92
    In this clear and up-to-date introduction, Thomas D. Senor lays the philosophical foundation needed to understand the justification of memory belief. This book explores traditional accounts of the justification of memory belief and examines the resources that prominent positions in contemporary epistemology have to offer theories of the memorial justification. Along the way, epistemic conservatism, evidentialism, foundationalism, phenomenal conservatism, reliabilism, and preservationism all feat…Read more
  •  36
    The Uniqueness Argument and Religious Rationality Pluralism
    Philosophia Christi 20 (1): 241-252. 2018.
    In this paper, I offer a defense of what I dub “religious rationality pluralism”—that is, that people of various religions can be rational in holding a variety of religious perspectives. I distinguish two arguments against this position: the Uniqueness argument and the Disagreement argument. The aims of this essay are to argue that the Uniqueness thesis is ambiguous between two readings, that while one version of the thesis is quite plausible, it cannot be successfully used to argue against rati…Read more
  •  1391
    A Critical Review of Alvin Plantinga’s Warranted Christian Belief (review)
    International Philosophical Quarterly 42 (3): 389-396. 2002.
  • Ongoing Justification: An Essay on the Epistemology of Memory
    Dissertation, The University of Arizona. 1989.
    Many accounts of epistemic justification are initially plausible as accounts of justifiably coming to believe a proposition, but fail as accounts of continuing to believe a proposition. In this essay, I examine candidate theories of ongoing justification, arguing that those along both coherentist and foundationalist lines are inadequate. First, I argue that coherentism doesn't work by dividing such accounts into negative and positive theories. Negative coherentism fails because of its dependence…Read more
  •  130
    Subjects of Experience
    Philosophical Review 112 (3): 416-419. 2003.
    Subjects of Experience is as ambitious as it is contrary to the spirit of most of contemporary analytic metaphysics and philosophy of mind. The reader needs a scorecard to keep track of all the currently unfashionable positions that Lowe adopts in this courageous little book. While the work ranges broadly over many topics, Lowe’s account of the self is at its core, and will be the focus of this review. However, it should be noted that one of the virtues of Subjects of Experience is its broad per…Read more
  •  966
    God, Supernatural Kinds, and the Incarnation
    Religious Studies 27 (3): 353-370. 1991.
    Traditionally, the term ’God’ has been understood either as a proper name or as a description. However, according to a new view, the term God’ in a sentence like "Jesus Christ is God" functions as a kind term, much as the term ’tiger’ functions in the sentence "Tigger is a tiger." In this paper I examine the claim that divinity can be construed as a ’supernatural’ kind, developing the outlines of an account of the semantics of God’ along these lines, and suggest that it might solve an important …Read more
  •  105
    Warrant (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 48 (4): 925-926. 1995.
  •  2169
    Defending Divine Freedom
    In L. Kvanvig Jonathan (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Oxford University Press. pp. 168-95. 2013.
  •  1092
    The Incarnation
    In Chad Meister & Paul Copan (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, Routledge Press. 2007.
  •  889
    The Incarnation and the Trinity
    In Michael J. Murray (ed.), Reason for the Hope Within, Wm. B. Eerdmans. 1999.
  •  2083
    Timothy O’Connor’s book Theism and Ultimate Explanation offers a defense of a new version of the cosmological argument. In his discussion, O’Connor argues against the coherence of a brute fact “explanation” of the universe and for the claim that the God of theism cannot be logically contingent. In this paper, I take issue with both of these arguments. Regarding the former, I claim that contrary to what O’Connor asserts, we have no good reason to prefer an account according to which the universe …Read more
  •  763
    Incarnation and Timeless
    Faith and Philosophy 7 (2): 149-164. 1990.
  •  18
    The Prima/Ultima Facie Justification Distinction in Epistemology
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (3): 551-566. 1996.
  •  20
    Common Core/Diversity Dilemma, Agatheism and the Epistemology of Religious Belief
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 8 (4): 213--226. 2016.
    The essay “The Common-Core/Diversity Dilemma: Revisions of Humean Thought, New Empirical Research, and the Limits of Rational Religious Belief‘ is a bold argument for the irrationality of “first-order‘ religious belief. However, unlike those associated with “New Atheism,‘ the paper’s authors Branden Thornhill-Miller and Peter Millican claim both that there are prospects for rational “second-order‘ religious belief and that religious belief and practice can play a positive role in human life. In …Read more
  •  633
    Review of Paul K. Moser, The Evidence for God: Religious Knowledge Reexamined (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2011 (1). 2011.
  •  87
    God, Supernatural Kinds, and the Incarnation: THOMAS D. SENOR
    Religious Studies 27 (3): 353-370. 1991.
    Thinking about God often leads to thinking about ‘God’. And it has never been completely clear how best to understand this little English word. Traditionally, ‘God’ has been taken to be either a description or a name. However, a third option has recently captured the attention of philosophical theologians. It is claimed that just as one should think of, say, ‘humanity’ as a kind term, so one should think of ‘God’, or perhaps ‘divinity’, as a kind term. But given the tight link between semantics …Read more
  •  827
    Drawing on Many Traditions: An Ecumenical Kenotic Christology
    In Anna Marmodoro & Jonathan Hill (eds.), The Metaphysics of the Incarnation, Oxford University Press. 2011.
  •  143
    The Knowledge-As-Perception Account of Knowledge
    Journal of Philosophical Research 41 (9999): 91-109. 2016.
    William Alston once argued that justification is not necessary for knowledge. He was convinced of this because he thought that, in cases of clear perception, one could come to know that P even if one’s justification for believing P was defeated. The idea is that the epistemic strength of clear perception is sufficient to provide knowledge even where justification is lacking; perceiving (and believing) that P is sufficient for knowing that P. In this paper, I explore a claim about knowledge that …Read more
  •  138
    Body and soul
    The Philosophers' Magazine 57 (57): 113-114. 2012.
  •  1054
    Preserving preservationism: A reply to Lackey
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74 (1). 2007.