•  186
    Hilbert's 'foundations of physics': Gravitation and electromagnetism within the axiomatic method
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (1): 102-153. 2008.
  •  161
    Recently discovered correspondence from Oskar Becker to Hermann Weyl sheds new light on Weyl's engagement with Husserlian transcendental phenomenology in 1918-1927. Here the last two of these letters, dated July and August, 1926, dealing with issues in the philosophy of mathematics are presented, together with background and a detailed commentary. The letters provide an instructive context for re-assessing the connection between intuitionism and phenomenology in Weyl's foundational thought, and …Read more
  •  122
    Cassirer and Dirac on the Symbolic Method in Quantum Mechanics: A Confluence of Opposites
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 6 (3). 2018.
    Determinismus und Indeterminismus in der modernen Physik is one of Cassirer’s least known and studied works, despite his own assessment as “one of his most important achievements”. A prominent theme locates quantum mechanics as a yet further step of the tendency within physical theory towards the purely functional theory of the concept and functional characterization of objectivity. In this respect DI can be considered an “update”, like the earlier monograph Zur Einsteinschen Relativitätstheorie…Read more
  •  104
    What does History Matter to Philosophy of Physics?
    Journal of the Philosophy of History 5 (3): 496-512. 2011.
    Naturalized metaphysics remains a default presupposition of much contemporary philosophy of physics. As metaphysics is supposed to be about the general structure of reality, so a naturalized metaphysics draws upon our best physical theories: Assuming the truth of such a theory, it attempts to answer the “foundational question par excellence “, “how could the world possibly be the way this theory says it is?“ It is argued that attention to historical detail in the development and formulation of p…Read more
  •  104
    Invariance Principles as Regulative Ideals: From Wigner to Hilbert: Thomas Ryckman
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 63 63-80. 2008.
    Eugene Wigner's several general discussions of symmetry and invariance principles are among the canonical texts of contemporary philosophy of physics. Wigner spoke from a position of authority, having pioneered for recognition of the importance of symmetry principles from nuclear to molecular physics. But perhaps recent commentators have not sufficiently stressed that Wigner always took care to situate the notion of invariance principles with respect to two others, initial conditions and laws of…Read more
  •  93
    In early major works, Cassirer and Schlick differently recast traditional doctrines of the concept and of the relation of concept to intuitive content along the lines of recent epistemological discussions within the exact sciences. In this, they attempted to refashion epistemology by incorporating as its basic principle the notion of functional coordination, the theoretical sciences' own methodological tool for dispensing with the imprecise and unreliable guide of intuitive evidence. Examining t…Read more
  •  84
    Weyl, Reichenbach and the epistemology of geometry
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (6): 831-870. 1994.
  •  84
    Universally recognized as bringing about a revolutionary transformation of the notions of space, time, and motion in physics, Einstein's theory of gravitation, known as "general relativity," was also a defining event for 20th century philosophy of science. During the decisive first ten years of the theory's existence, two main tendencies dominated its philosophical reception. This book is an extended argument that the path actually taken, which became logical empiricist philosophy of science, gr…Read more
  •  81
    Review. Carnap's construction of the world: The aufbau and the emergence of logical empiricism (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 50 (3): 497-500. 1999.
  •  75
  •  73
    Revised Factualism
    The Monist 77 (2): 207-216. 1994.
    I shall argue that those who hold that there are factual complexes, or facts, and who subscribe to a correspondence theory of truth, according to which truth is analyzed in terms of correspondence to facts, need not hold that, in addition to facts, there are propositions.
  •  73
    Contingency, a prioricity and acquaintance
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): 323-343. 1993.
  •  62
  •  60
    Chaos, Clio, and Scientistic Illusions of Understanding
    History and Theory 34 (1): 30-44. 1995.
    A number of authors have recently argued that the mathematical insights of "chaos theory" offer a promising formal model or significant analogy for understanding at least some historical events. We examine a representative claim of each kind regarding the application of chaos theory to problems of historical explanation. We identify two lines of argument. One we term the Causal Thesis, which states that chaos theory may be used to plausibly model, and so explain, historical events. The other we …Read more
  •  57
    On believing, saying and expressing
    Synthese 79 (2). 1989.
    Examines the connections among believing, saying, and expressing in situations where the sentence used is a declarative sentence containing at least one proper name. Proposes a new way of understanding these connections. Develops an argument for the thesis that, although we typically believe the singular propositions expressed by our uses of name sentences, we rarely use such sentences because we believe those propositions.
  •  48
    Metaphysics Avoidance: Mark Wilson and Ernst Cassirer
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 103 (2): 466-472. 2021.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Volume 103, Issue 2, Page 466-472, September 2021.
  •  46
    Belief, linguistic behavior, and propositional content
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (2): 277-287. 1986.
  •  39
    Einstein, Cassirer, and General Covariance — Then and Now
    Science in Context 12 (4): 585-619. 1999.
    The ArgumentRecent archival research has brought about a new understanding of the import of Einstein's puzzling remarks (1916) attributing a physical meaning to general covariance. Debates over the scope and meaning of general covariance still persist, even within physics. But already in 1921 Cassirer identified the significance of general covariance as a novel stage in the development of the criterion of objectivity within physics; an account of this development, and its implications, is the pr…Read more
  •  38
    Otto Neurath: Philosophy between Science and Politics (review)
    with Nancy Cartwright, Jordi Cat, Lola Fleck, and Thomas E. Uebel
    Philosophical Review 107 (2): 327. 1998.
    Four distinguished authors have been brought together to produce this elegant study of a much-neglected figure. The book is divided into three sections: Neurath's biographical background and the economic and social context of his ideas; his theory of science; and the development of his role in debates on Marxist concepts of history and his own conception of science. Coinciding with the emerging serious interest in logical positivism, this timely publication will redress a current imbalance in th…Read more
  •  35
    Dickie on artifactuality
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 47 (2): 175-177. 1989.
  •  27