•  1
    Review (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (1): 185-188. 1998.
  •  17
    Complementarity Revisited
    Foundations of Science 25 (2): 401-424. 2020.
    Complementarity can be considered as the weirdest idea associated with quantum mechanics. For Bohr, Complementarity is important in order to be able to convey successfully the non-classical features of quantum mechanics. This paper discusses the epistemic and ontological implications of different new experiments that attempt to detect complementarity. Complementarity has surely survived the attempts to overcome it, yet some of these experiments have led to a more general form of complementarity.…Read more
  •  173
    Modelling in applied physics: The case of polymers
    Dirasat, Pure Science 33 (2): 241-250. 2006.
    Until recently philosophy of physics has been overshadowed by the idea that the important philosophical issues that can be derived from physics are related only to fundamental theories, such as quantum mechanics and relativity. Applied fields of physics were deemed as unimportant. The argument for such a position lays in thinking that these applied fields of physics depend in their theoretical representations on fundamental theories and hence are reducible to these fundamental theories. It would…Read more
  •  1032
    The tool box of science: Tools for the building of models with a superconductivity example
    with Nancy Cartwright and Mauricio Suárez
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 44 137-149. 1995.
    We call for a new philosophical conception of models in physics. Some standard conceptions take models to be useful approximations to theorems, that are the chief means to test theories. Hence the heuristics of model building is dictated by the requirements and practice of theory-testing. In this paper we argue that a theory-driven view of models can not account for common procedures used by scientists to model phenomena. We illustrate this thesis with a case study: the construction of one of th…Read more
  •  455
    Bohr as a Phenomenological Realist
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 39 (2): 321-349. 2008.
    There is confusion among scholars of Bohr as to whether he should be categorized as an instrumentalist (see Faye 1991) or a realist (see Folse 1985). I argue that Bohr is a realist, and that the confusion is due to the fact that he holds a very special view of realism, which did not coincide with the philosophers’ views. His approach was sometimes labelled instrumentalist and other times realist, because he was an instrumentalist on the theoretical level, but a realist on the level of models. Su…Read more
  •  277
    Correspondence Principle
    In Neil Salkind (ed.), Encyclopaedia of Research Design, Vol. 1, Sage Publications. pp. 168-174. 2010.
    A comprehensive look at the kinds of correspondence principle in physics.
  •  295
    Phenomenologism vs fundamentalism: The case of superconductivity
    CURRENT SCIENCE, 94 (10): 1256-1264. 2008.
    This article argues that phenomenological treatment of physical problems is more powerful than fundamental treatment. Developments in the field of superconductivity present us with a clear example of such superiority. The BCS (Bardeen, Cooper and Schrieffer) was accepted as the fundamental theory of superconductivity for a long time. Nevertheless, Landau and Ginzburg phenomenological model has so far proven to be a more fruitful theoretical representation to understand and to predict the feature…Read more