-
1240The Hard Problem of ResponsibilityIn David Shoemaker (ed.), Oxford Studies in Agency and Responsibility, Volume 1, Oxford University Press Uk. 2013.
-
739The Empowering Theory of TrustIn Paul Faulkner & Thomas Simpson (eds.), The Philosophy of Trust, Oxford University Press. pp. 14-34. 2017.
-
596Intelligent capacities in artificial systemsIn William A. Bauer & Anna Marmodoro (eds.), Artificial Dispositions: Investigating Ethical and Metaphysical Issues, Bloomsbury. 2023.This paper investigates the nature of dispositional properties in the context of artificial intelligence systems. We start by examining the distinctive features of natural dispositions according to criteria introduced by McGeer (2018) for distinguishing between object-centered dispositions (i.e., properties like ‘fragility’) and agent-based abilities, including both ‘habits’ and ‘skills’ (a.k.a. ‘intelligent capacities’, Ryle 1949). We then explore to what extent the distinction applies to artif…Read more
-
429Managing shame and guilt in addiction: A pathway to recoveryAddictive Behaviors 120. 2021.A dominant view of guilt and shame is that they have opposing action tendencies: guilt- prone people are more likely to avoid or overcome dysfunctional patterns of behaviour, making amends for past misdoings, whereas shame-prone people are more likely to persist in dysfunctional patterns of behaviour, avoiding responsibility for past misdoings and/or lashing out in defensive aggression. Some have suggested that addiction treatment should make use of these insights, tailoring therapy according to…Read more
-
375Trust, hope and empowermentAustralasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (2). 2008.Philosophers and social scientists have focussed a great deal of attention on our human capacity to trust, but relatively little on the capacity to hope. This is a significant oversight, as hope and trust are importantly interconnected. This paper argues that, even though trust can and does feed our hopes, it is our empowering capacity to hope that significantly underwrites—and makes rational—our capacity to trust.
-
307Mind-making practices: the social infrastructure of self-knowing agency and responsibilityPhilosophical Explorations 18 (2): 259-281. 2015.This paper is divided into two parts. In Section 1, I explore and defend a “regulative view” of folk-psychology as against the “standard view”. On the regulative view, folk-psychology is conceptualized in fundamentally interpersonal terms as a “mind-making” practice through which we come to form and regulate our minds in accordance with a rich array of socially shared and socially maintained sense-making norms. It is not, as the standard view maintains, simply an epistemic capacity for coming to…Read more
-
301Scaffolding agency: A proleptic account of the reactive attitudesEuropean Journal of Philosophy 27 (2): 301-323. 2018.This paper examines the methodological claim made famous by P.F. Strawson: that we understand what features are required for responsible agency by exploring our attitudes and practices of holding responsible. What is the presumed metaphysical connection between holding responsible and being fit to be held responsible that makes this claim credible? I propose a non-standard answer to this question, arguing for a view of responsible agency that is neither anti-realist (i.e. purely 'conventionali…Read more
-
256The Moral Development of First‐Person AuthorityEuropean Journal of Philosophy 16 (1): 81-108. 2008.
-
247Is Morality Unified? Evidence that Distinct Neural Systems Underlie Moral Judgments of Harm, Dishonesty, and DisgustJournal of Cognitive Neuroscience 23 (10): 3162-3180. 2011.Much recent research has sought to uncover the neural basis of moral judgment. However, it has remained unclear whether "moral judgments" are sufficiently homogenous to be studied scientifically as a unified category. We tested this assumption by using fMRI to examine the neural correlates of moral judgments within three moral areas: (physical) harm, dishonesty, and (sexual) disgust. We found that the judgment ofmoral wrongness was subserved by distinct neural systems for each of the different m…Read more
-
208Is "Self-Knowledge" an Empirical Problem? Renegotiating the Space of Philosophical ExplanationJournal of Philosophy 93 (10): 483-515. 1996.
-
207Autistic self-awareness: CommentPhilosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 11 (3): 235-251. 2004.A currently popular view traces autistic cognitive abnormalities to a defective capacity for theorizing about other minds. Two prominent researchers, Uta Frith and Francesca Happé, extend this account by tracing further autistic abnormalities to impaired self-consciousness. This paper argues that Frith and Happé's account requires a treatment of autistic self-report that is problematic on both methodological and philosophical grounds. However, the philosophical problems point to an alternative a…Read more
-
181The regulative dimension of folk psychologyIn Daniel D. Hutto & Matthew Ratcliffe (eds.), Folk Psychology Re-Assessed, Springer Press. pp. 137--156. 2007.
-
179XV—Intelligent CapacitiesProceedings of the Aristotelian Society 118 (3). 2018.In The Concept of Mind, Gilbert Ryle argued that a more sophisticated understanding of the dispositional nature of ‘intelligent capacities’ could bolster philosophical resistance to the tempting view that the human mind is possessed of metaphysically ‘occult’ powers and properties. This temptation is powerful in the context of accounting for the special qualities of responsible agency. Incompatibilists indulge the temptation; compatibilists resist it, using a variety of strategies. One recen…Read more
-
179Why Neuroscience Matters to Cognitive NeuropsychologySynthese 159 (3). 2007.The broad issue in this paper is the relationship between cognitive psychology and neuroscience. That issue arises particularly sharply for cognitive neurospsychology, some of whose practitioners claim a methodological autonomy for their discipline. They hold that behavioural data from neuropsychological impairments are sufficient to justify assumptions about the underlying modular structure of human cognitive architecture, as well as to make inferences about its various components. But this cla…Read more
-
162Psycho-practice, psycho-theory and the contrastive case of autism: How practices of mind become second-natureJournal of Consciousness Studies 8 (5-7): 109-132. 2001.In philosophy, the last thirty years or so has seen a split between 'simulation theorists' and 'theory-theorists', with a number of variations on each side. In general, simulation theorists favour the idea that our knowledge of others is based on using ourselves as a working model of what complex psychological creatures are like. Theory-theorists claim that our knowledge of complex psychological creatures, including ourselves, is theoretical in character and so more like our knowledge of the wor…Read more
-
160Building a better theory of responsibilityPhilosophical Studies 172 (10): 2635-2649. 2015.In Building Better Beings, Vargas develops and defends a naturalistic account of responsibility, whereby responsible agents must possess a feasibly situated capacity to detect and respond to moral considerations. As a preliminary step, he also offers a substantive account of how we might justify our practices of holding responsible—viz., by appeal to their efficacy in fostering a ‘valuable form of agency’ across the community at large, a form of agency that precisely encompasses sensitivity to m…Read more
-
118The trouble with MaryPacific Philosophical Quarterly 84 (4): 384-393. 2003.Two arguments are famously held to support the conclusion that consciousness cannot be explained in purely physical or functional terms – hence, that physicalism is false: the modal argument and the knowledge argument. While anti‐physicalists appeal to both arguments, this paper argues there is a methodological incoherence in jointly maintaining them: the modal argument supports the possibility of zombies; but the possibility of zombies undercuts the knowledge argument. At best, this leaves anti…Read more
-
116The thought and talk of individuals with autism: Reflections on Ian HackingMetaphilosophy 40 (3-4): 517-530. 2009.Ian Hacking proposes that ways of talking about autistic experience can shape, or even transform, what it is like to be autistic. I explore the grounds for two nonexclusive interpretations of this thesis. The informative interpretation holds that, because nonautistics cannot read mental states into autistic behaviour as they normally do with one another, autistic self‐narratives give nonautistics unique insights into what it is like to be autistic. This in turn affects how nonautistics interact …Read more
-
115Enculturating folk psychologistsSynthese 199 (1-2): 1039-1063. 2020.This paper argues that our folk-psychological expertise is a special case of extended and enculturated cognition where we learn to regulate both our own and others’ thought and action in accord with a wide array of culturally shaped folk-psychological norms. The view has three noteworthy features: it challenges a common assumption that the foundational capacity at work in folk-psychological expertise is one of interpreting behaviour in mentalistic terms, arguing instead that successful mindreadi…Read more
-
104Mindshaping is Inescapable, Social Injustice is not: Reflections on Haslanger’s Critical Social TheoryTandf: Australasian Philosophical Review 3 (1): 48-59. 2019.Volume 3, Issue 1, March 2019, Page 48-59.
-
89Developing trustPhilosophical Explorations 5 (1). 2002.This paper examines developing trust in two related senses: (1) rationally overcoming distrust, and (2) developing a mature capacity for trusting/distrusting. In focussing exclusively on the first problem, traditional philosophical discussions fail to address how an evidence- based paradigm of rationality is easily co-opted by (immature) agents in support of irrational distrust (or trust) - a manifestation of the second problem. Well-regulated trust requires developing a capacity to tolerate the…Read more
-
85The Value of Reactive Attitudes: Critical Response to Christine Tappolet's Emotions, Values and AgencyPhilosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (2): 512-519. 2018.
-
78The Art of Good HopeAnnals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science (1): 100--127. 2004.What is hope? Though variously characterized as a cognitive attitude, an emotion, a disposition, and even a process or activity, hope, more deeply, a unifying and grounding force of human agency. We cannot live a human life without hope, therefore questions about the rationality of hope are properly recast as questions about what it means to hope well. This thesis is defended and elaborated as follows. First, it is argued that hope is an essential and distinctive feature of human agency, both co…Read more
-
74Are ‘Optimistic’ Theories of Criminal Justice Psychologically Feasible? The Probative Case of Civic RepublicanismCriminal Law and Philosophy 11 (3): 523-544. 2017.‘Optimistic’ normative theories of criminal justice aim to justify criminal sanction in terms of its reprobative/rehabilitative value rather than its punitive nature as such. But do such theories accord with ordinary intuitions about what constitutes a ‘just’ response to wrongdoing? Recent empirical work on the psychology of punishers suggests that human beings have a ‘brutely retributive’ moral psychology, making them unlikely to endorse normative theories that sacrifice retribution for the sak…Read more
-
67Philip Gerrans and Victoria McGeer
-
65
-
62Constructing agents: Rethinking the how and what in developmental theories of social understandingBehavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (1): 115-115. 2004.Although I am broadly in sympathy with Carpendale & Lewis's (C&L's) version of social constructivism, I raise two issues they might address. One bears on the question of how social understanding develops: Is their resistance to individualism inappropriately combined with a resistance to internalism? A second question concerns a more radical implication of their view for what social understanding is.
-
57Out of the mouths of autistics: Subjective report and its role in cognitive theorizingIn Andrew Brook & Kathleen Akins (eds.), Cognition and the Brain: The Philosophy and Neuroscience Movement, Cambridge University Press. pp. 98. 2005.
Areas of Specialization
8 more