•  360
    Moral responsibility and the psychopath
    Neuroethics 1 (3): 158-166. 2008.
    Psychopathy involves impaired capacity for prudential and moral reasoning due to impaired capacity for empathy, remorse, and sensitivity to fear-inducing stimuli. Brain abnormalities and genetic polymorphisms associated with these traits appear to justify the claim that psychopaths cannot be morally responsible for their behavior. Yet psychopaths are capable of instrumental reasoning in achieving their goals, which suggests that they have some capacity to respond to moral reasons against perform…Read more
  •  359
    Depression as a Mind-Body Problem
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 9 (3): 243-254. 2002.
    Major depression is a disorder of the mind caused by dysfunction of both the body and the brain. Because it is a psychiatric illness and psychiatry is a branch of medicine, the question of how mind and body interact in depression should be treated as a medical rather than metaphysical mind-body problem. The relation between mind and body as it pertains to this illness should be construed in teleological rather than causal terms. Mental states like beliefs and emotions serve an adaptive purpose b…Read more
  •  298
    The Neurodynamics of Free Will
    Mind and Matter 18 (2): 159-173. 2020.
  •  262
    Key Concepts: Endophenotypes
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 10 (3): 277-284. 2003.
    Endophenotypes are an exciting and important area of research in genetically complex psychiatric diseases. They are biological markers between genotype and external phenotype that may indicate susceptibility to or manifest as early signs of a wide range of mental disorders. Identifying endophenotypes can enable researchers to tease apart the biological components of psychiatric diseases and thereby gain a better understanding of them. They may lead to more accurate prediction and to more effecti…Read more
  •  256
    Neurobiology, neuroimaging, and free will
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 29 (1): 68-82. 2005.
  •  186
    Psychopharmacological enhancement
    Neuroethics 1 (1): 45-54. 2008.
    Many drugs have therapeutic off-label uses for which they were not originally designed. Some drugs designed to treat neuropsychiatric and other disorders may enhance certain normal cognitive and affective functions. Because the long-term effects of cognitive and affective enhancement are not known and may be harmful, a precautionary principle limiting its use seems warranted. As an expression of autonomy, though, competent individuals should be permitted to take cognition- and mood-enhancing age…Read more
  •  181
    Advances in genetic technology in general and medical genetics in particular will enable us to intervene in the process of human biological development which extends from zygotes and embryos to people. This will allow us to control to a great extent the identities and the length and quality of the lives of people who already exist, as well as those we bring into existence in the near and distant future. Genes and Future People explores two general philosophical questions, one metaphysical, the o…Read more
  •  173
    Brain implants, such as Deep Brain Stimulation (DBS), which are designed to improve motor, mood and behavioural pathology, present unique challenges to our understanding of identity, agency and free will. This is because these devices can have visible effects on persons' physical and psychological properties yet are essentially undetectable when operating correctly. They can supplement and compensate for one's inherent abilities and faculties when they are compromised by neuropsychiatric disorde…Read more
  •  172
    Our brains are not us
    Bioethics 23 (6): 321-329. 2009.
    Many neuroscientists have claimed that our minds are just a function of and thus reducible to our brains. I challenge neuroreductionism by arguing that the mind emerges from and is shaped by interaction among the brain, body, and environment. The mind is not located in the brain but is distributed among these three entities. I then explore the implications of the distributed mind for neuroethics.
  •  141
    Neuroethics
    Bioethics 20 (1). 2005.
    Neuroimaging, psychosurgery, deep-brain stimulation, and psychopharmacology hold considerable promise for more accurate prediction and diagnosis and more effective treatment of neurological and psychiatric disorders. Some forms of psychopharmacology may even be able to enhance normal cognitive and affective capacities. But the brain remains the most complex and least understood of all the organs in the human body. Mapping the neural correlates of the mind through brain scans, and altering these …Read more
  •  133
    The Case against Conscription of Cadaveric Organs for Transplantation
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 17 (3): 330-336. 2008.
    In a recent set of papers, Aaron Spital has proposed conscription or routine recovery of cadaveric organs without consent as a way of ameliorating the severe shortage of organs for transplantation. Under the existing consent requirement, organs can be taken from the bodies of the deceased if they expressed a wish and intention to donate while alive. Organs may also be taken when families or other substitute decisionmakers decide on behalf of the deceased to allow organ procurement for the purpos…Read more
  •  131
    Responsibility and Priority in Liver Transplantation
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 18 (1): 23-35. 2009.
    In a provocative 1991 paper, Alvin Moss and Mark Siegler argued that it may be fair to give individuals with alcohol-related end-stage liver disease lower priority for a liver transplant than those who develop end-stage liver disease from other factors. Like other organs, there is a substantial gap between the available livers for transplantation and the number of people who need liver transplants. Yet, unlike those with end-stage renal disease, who can survive for some time on dialysis before r…Read more
  •  129
    Moral Responsibility and Personal Identity
    American Philosophical Quarterly 35 (3). 1998.
  •  118
    Obsessions, Compulsions, and Free Will
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 19 (4): 333-337. 2012.
    Obsessive-compulsive disorder (OCD) and other psychiatric disorders can interfere with a person’s capacity to control the nature of his mental states and how they issue in his decisions and actions. Insofar as this sort of control is identified with free will, and psychiatric disorders can impair this control, these disorders can impair free will. The will can be compromised by dysregulated neural networks that disable the mental mechanisms necessary to regulate thought, motivation, and action. …Read more
  •  112
    Responsibility, alcoholism, and liver transplantation
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 23 (1). 1998.
    Many believe that it is morally wrong to give lower priority for a liver transplant to alcoholics with end-stage liver disease than to patients whose disease is not alcohol-related. Presumably, alcoholism is a disease that results from factors beyond one's control and therefore one cannot be causally or morally responsible for alcoholism or the liver failure that results from it. Moreover, giving lower priority to alcoholics unfairly singles them out for the moral vice of heavy drinking. I argue…Read more
  •  107
    Neurostimulation to restore cognitive and physical functions is an innovative and promising technique for treating patients with severe brain injury that has resulted in a minimally conscious state (MCS). The technique may involve electrical stimulation of the central thalamus, which has extensive projections to the cerebral cortex. Yet it is unclear whether an improvement in neurological functions would result in a net benefit for these patients. Quality-of-life measurements would be necessary …Read more
  •  99
  •  97
    The Psychology and Physiology of Depression
    Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 9 (3): 265-269. 2002.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology 9.3 (2002) 265-269 [Access article in PDF] The Psychology and Physiology of Depression Walter Glannon Trauma and stressful events can disrupt the physiologic homeostasis of our bodies and brains. The physiologic stress response consists of neural and endocrine mechanisms whose function is to reestablish homeostasis. These mechanisms include the secretion of glucocorticoids (cortisol) and catechole…Read more
  •  85
    Beyond Consent in Research
    with Emily Bell, Eric Racine, Paula Chiasson, Maya Dufourcq-Brana, Laura B. Dunn, Joseph J. Fins, Paul J. Ford, Nir Lipsman, Mary Ellen Macdonald, Debra J. H. Mathews, and Mary Pat Mcandrews
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 23 (3): 361-368. 2014.
    Abstract:Vulnerability is an important criterion to assess the ethical justification of the inclusion of participants in research trials. Currently, vulnerability is often understood as an attribute inherent to a participant by nature of a diagnosed condition. Accordingly, a common ethical concern relates to the participant’s decisionmaking capacity and ability to provide free and informed consent. We propose an expanded view of vulnerability that moves beyond a focus on consent and the intrinsi…Read more
  •  84
    Intervening in the psychopath’s brain
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 35 (1): 43-57. 2014.
    Psychopathy is a disorder involving personality and behavioral features associated with a high rate of violent aggression and recidivism. This paper explores potential psychopharmacological therapies to modulate dysfunctional neural pathways in psychopaths and reduce the incidence of their harmful behavior, as well as the ethical and legal implications of offering these therapies as an alternative to incarceration. It also considers whether forced psychopharmacological intervention in adults and…Read more
  •  75
    Temporal Asymmetry, Life, and Death
    American Philosophical Quarterly 31 (3). 1994.
  •  74
    Recent advances in human genetics suggest that it may become possible to genetically manipulate telomerase and embryonic stem cells to alter the mechanisms of aging and extend the human life span. But a life span significantly longer than the present norm would be undesirable because it would severely weaken the connections between past‐ and future‐oriented mental states and in turn the psychological grounds for personal identity and prudential concern for our future selves. In addition, the col…Read more
  •  74
    Brain, Behavior, and Knowledge
    Neuroethics 4 (3): 191-194. 2010.
    In “Minds, Brains, and Norms,” Michael Pardo and Dennis Patterson claim that the idea that ‘you are your brain’ does not contribute to a plausible account of human behavior. I argue that they leave too little of the brain in their account of different types of behavior
  •  73
    Semicompatibilism and anomalous monism
    Philosophical Papers 26 (3): 211-231. 1997.
  •  71
    Ben Bradley, well-being and death (review)
    Journal of Value Inquiry 44 (1): 107-111. 2010.
  •  70
    Extending the human life span
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 27 (3). 2002.
    Research into the mechanisms of aging has suggested the possibility of extending the human life span. But there may be evolutionary biological reasons for senescence and the limits of the cell cycle that explain the infirmities of aging and the eventual demise of all human organisms. Genetic manipulation of the mechanisms of aging could over many generations alter the course of natural selection and shift the majority of deleterious mutations in humans from later to earlier stages of life. This …Read more
  •  67
    Deep-brain stimulation for depression
    HEC Forum 20 (4): 325-335. 2008.
  •  66
    Epicureanism and Death
    The Monist 76 (2): 222-234. 1993.
    Perhaps the most frequently cited argument in philosophical discussions of death is the one embodied in the following passage from Epicurus’ Letter to Menoeceus