USC
Department Of Philosophy
Alumnus
Boston, Massachusetts, United States of America
  •  273
    Conceptualism and the myth of the given
    European Journal of Philosophy 17 (3): 363-385. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  237
    How to Think About Nonconceptual Content
    The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 10 (1): 1-24. 2010.
    This paper provides a general account of what nonconceptual content is, and some considerations in favor of its existence. After distinguishing between the contents and objects of mental states, as well as the properties of being conceptual and being conceptualized, I argue that what is phenomenologically distinctive about conceptual content is that it is not determined by, and does not determine, the intuitive character of an experience. That is, for virtually any experience E with intuitive ch…Read more
  •  207
    Husserl on sensation, perception, and interpretation
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (2): 219-245. 2008.
    Husserl's theory of perception is remarkable in several respects. For one thing, Husserl rigorously distinguishes the parts and properties of the act of consciousness - its content -from the parts and properties of the object perceived. Second, Husserl's repeated insistence that perceptual consciousness places its subject in touch with the perceived object itself, rather than some representation that does duty for it, vindicates the commonsensical and phenomenologically grounded belief that when…Read more
  •  175
    Husserl, Dummett, and the Linguistic Turn
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 78 (1): 17-40. 2009.
    Michael Dummett famously holds that the “philosophy of thought” must proceed via the philosophy of language, since that is the only way to preserve the objectivity of thoughts while avoiding commitments to “mythological,” Platonic entities. Central to Dummett’s case is his thesis that all thought contents are linguistically expressible. In this paper, I will (a) argue that making the linguistic turn is neither necessary nor sufficient to avoid the problems of psychologism, (b) discuss Wayne Ma…Read more
  •  129
    Husserl, phenomenology, and foundationalism
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (2). 2008.
    Husserl is often taken, and not without reason, to endorse the view that phenomenology's task is to provide the “absolute foundation” of human knowledge. In this paper, I will argue that the most natural interpretation of this view, namely that all human knowledge depends for its justification, at least in part, on phenomenological knowledge, is philosophically untenable. I will also present evidence that Husserl himself held no such view, and will argue that Dan Zahavi and John Drummond, though…Read more
  •  124
    No such look: problems with the dual content theory
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (4): 813-833. 2013.
    It is frequently alleged that a round plate viewed from an oblique angle looks elliptical, and that when one tree is in front of another that is the same intrinsic size, the front one looks larger than the rear one. And yet there is also a clear sense in which the plate viewed from an angle looks round, and a clear sense in which the two trees look to be the same size. According to the Dual Content Theory (DCT), what explains these and other similar phenomena is that perceptual experiences prese…Read more
  •  123
    Perception and Knowledge: A Phenomenological Account
    Cambridge University Press. 2011.
    This book offers a provocative, clear and rigorously argued account of the nature of perception and its role in the production of knowledge. Walter Hopp argues that perceptual experiences do not have conceptual content, and that what makes them play a distinctive epistemic role is not the features which they share with beliefs, but something that in fact sets them radically apart. He explains that the reason-giving relation between experiences and beliefs is what Edmund Husserl called 'fulfilmen…Read more
  •  110
    Phenomenology and fallibility
    Husserl Studies 25 (1): 1-14. 2009.
    If Husserl is correct, phenomenological inquiry produces knowledge with an extremely high level of epistemic warrant or justification. However, there are several good reasons to think that we are highly fallible at carrying out phenomenological inquiries. It is extremely difficult to engage in phenomenological investigations, and there are very few substantive phenomenological claims that command a widespread consensus. In what follows, I introduce a distinction between method-fallibility and ag…Read more
  •  94
    This is a response to Charles Travis's article "Is Seeing Intentional?" In it, I argue that while seeing differs from other intentional states in a variety of ways, seeing is indeed intentional, at least in the philosophically central sense of "intentional" introduced to us by Brentano and Husserl. Seeing is, quite often at least, the consciousness of something. I spend the majority of the paper discussing Travis's arguments that it is not, and providing reasons for thinking they are inconclusiv…Read more
  •  83
    Image Consciousness and the Horizonal Structure of Perception
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 41 (1): 130-153. 2017.
  •  70
    Reply to Heffernan
    Husserl Studies 25 (1): 45-49. 2009.
    If Husserl is correct, phenomenological inquiry produces knowledge with an extremely high level of epistemic warrant or justification. However, there are several good reasons to think that we are highly fallible at carrying out phenomenological inquiries. It is extremely difficult to engage in phenomenological investigations, and there are very few substantive phenomenological claims that command a widespread consensus. In what follows, I introduce a distinction between method-fallibility and ag…Read more
  •  56
    Experiments in Thought
    Perspectives on Science 22 (2): 242-263. 2014.
    . What are thought experiments, and how do they generate knowledge? More specifically, what sorts of intentional acts must one perform in order to carry out a thought experiment, what sorts of objects are such acts directed toward, and how are those objects made present in such acts? I argue on phenomenological grounds that the proper objects of thought experiments are, in certain cases, uninstantiated universals and relations among them. I will also argue that, in the best of cases, we intuit o…Read more
  •  46
    The Philosophy of Edmund Husserl (review)
    Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 29 (2): 175-184. 2008.
  •  36
    Minimalist Truth and Realist Truth
    Philosophia Christi 10 (1): 87-100. 2008.
    I examine and reject Alston’s minimalist realism. According to minimalist realism, anyone who grasps the “conceptual necessity” of any arbitrary instance of the schema “The proposition that p is true if and only if p” will thereby have acquired a realist conception of truth. After clarifying the sense in which Alston’s theory is “minimal,” I argue that, given plausible constraints on a realist theory of truth, grasping the necessity of any instance of the T-schema is far from sufficient to quali…Read more
  •  34
    Replies
    Husserl Studies 29 (1): 65-77. 2013.
    I would like to thank Sonja Rinofner-Kreidl and Søren Overgaard for their penetrating and challenging criticisms of my book, Perception and Knowledge (henceforth ‘‘PK’’). What follows are responses to some, though by no means all, of the critical points each raises.
  •  28
    "The central task of phenomenology is to investigate the nature of consciousness and its relations to objects of various types. The present book introduces students and other readers to several foundational topics of phenomenological inquiry, and illustrates phenomenology's contemporary relevance. The main topics include consciousness, intentionality, perception, meaning, and knowledge. The book also contains critical assessments of Edmund Husserl's phenomenological method. It argues that knowle…Read more
  •  28
    How to Think about Nonconceptual Content
    New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 10 (1): 1-24. 2010.
  •  19
    This volume identifies and develops how philosophy of mind and phenomenology interact in both conceptual and empirically-informed ways. The objective is to demonstrate that phenomenology, as the first-personal study of the contents and structures of our mentality, can provide us with insights into the understanding of the mind and can complement strictly analytical or empirically informed approaches to the study of the mind. Insofar as phenomenology, as the study or science of phenomena, allows …Read more
  •  17
    The (Many) Foundations of Knowledge
    In Dan Zahavi (ed.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology, Oxford University Press. 2012.
    This paper presents the outlines of a phenomenological theory of foundational or non-inferential knowledge according to which the facts or states of affairs towards which our beliefs are intentionally directed can sometimes serve as reasons or evidence for what we believe. This occurs in acts of fulfillment, in which an object or state of affairs is given as it is thought to be. Hopp further argues that the sorts of empirical facts that can serve as reasons for noninferentially justified beliefs…Read more
  • Phenomenal conservatism and the principle of all principles
    In D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou & W. Hopp (eds.), Philosophy of mind and phenomenology, Routledge. 2016.