•  1
    Leibniz Lexicon
    with Reinhard Finster, Graeme Hunter, Robert F. Mcrae, and Murray Miles
    Springer. 1990.
  •  3
    Scientific Anti-Realism and the Epistemic Community
    PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988 (1): 181-187. 1988.
    The ability to observe is the ability to reliably detect, but that is not all observation is. A thermometer reliably detects temperature yet does not observe the temperature, whereas I do, even though in terms of reliability I cannot match the thermometer. An observation is detection accompanied by active classification and, typically, the subsequent formation of opinion. Even when we say of an animal that it can see something we mean more than that it reliably detects things of a certain sort b…Read more
  •  1
    Physicalism
    In W. H. Newton‐Smith (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science, Blackwell. 2017.
    The crudest formulation of physicalism is simply the claim that everything is physical, and perhaps that is all physicalism ought to imply. But in fact a large number of distinct versions of physicalism are currently in play, with very different commitments and implications. There is no agreement about the detailed formulation of the doctrine, even though a majority of philosophers would claim to be physicalists, and a vast majority of them are physicalists of one sort or another. There are seve…Read more
  •  15
    Representationalism about Consciousness
    In Susan Schneider & Max Velmans (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Consciousness, Wiley. 2017.
    Modern representationalism about consciousness (MR) is often conflated with classical representationalism (CR). This chapter discusses CR first in order to highlight the contrast between old and new representationalism and bring out some of the strengths of the latter. It discerns three key projects related to MR. The first is that of determining whether its defining claim, the exhaustion thesis, is true. The second is that of explicating the fundamental difference between phenomenal and nonphen…Read more
  •  3
    Leibniz
    In W. H. Newton‐Smith (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science, Blackwell. 2017.
    Although one of the most important and prolific thinkers of all time, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) spent his life as a courtier, wasting time in diplomatic business or preparing documents to shore up claims of lineage or territory for his patrons. He also spent a good deal of time on practical matters of engineering, such as his dreams of a system of windmills that would have ameliorated the chronic flooding of the Harz silver mines, and on his visionary mechanical calculators. Most of …Read more
  •  1
    Supervenience and Determination
    In W. H. Newton‐Smith (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science, Blackwell. 2017.
    In the mid‐part of the twentieth century, the union of youthful science and the ancient philosophical dream of metaphysical completion begot a visionary doctrine known as the unity of science (see unity of science). This view of the relationship among scientific theories maintained that any theory aspiring to be truly “scientific” must fit into a hierarchy in which every theory was reducible to the theory immediately below it, save for the foundational theory of physics. Reduction would be accom…Read more
  •  1
    Metaphysics, Role in Science
    In W. H. Newton‐Smith (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Science, Blackwell. 2017.
    We must begin with the admission that the term “metaphysics” does not have a very precise or agreed upon meaning (no more does “science”). In current philosophy of science, “metaphysics” is, by and large, a pejorative term applied to whatever is regarded as illicitly nonempirical. Traditionally, metaphysics is regarded as the study of what lies behind the world of appearance ‐ perhaps constitutes that world, but is itself the only true reality. Obviously, a great many people would regard science…Read more
  •  6
    Scientific Anti‐Realism and the Philosophy of Mind
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 67 (2): 136-151. 1986.
  •  1
    Naturalizing the Mind (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (1): 83-109. 1997.
  • Emergence and efficacy
    In Christina E. Erneling & David Martel Johnson (eds.), The Mind as a Scientific Object: Between Brain and Culture, Oup Usa. 2005.
  •  11
    Transitivity, Introspection, and Conceptuality
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 20 (11-12): 31-50. 2013.
  •  1
    Panpsychism
    In Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  51
    Reduction and Emergence in Philosophy and Science
    Analysis 78 (3): 552-557. 2018.
    This book sets the standard, and a very high one at that, for the ongoing discussion of emergence in philosophy and science.1 1 Engaging but rigorous in argumentation, comprehensive but attentive to detail, it is a model of philosophical writing.
  •  91
    Reply to Forbes
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 42 (4): 224-226. 1982.
  •  10
    The Anomalousness of the Mental
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 19 (3): 389-401. 1981.
  • Materialism and the Foundations of Representation
    Dissertation, University of Toronto (Canada). 1981.
    This thesis divides into two main sections. The first is an attempt to show that the Psycho-physical Identity Theory is false, and is so even if we grant that human behaviour is in principle completely explicable in purely physical terms . This section is a sustained criticism of a staight-forward argument in favour of the Identity Theory, namely: Mental items cause behaviour. All behaviour is caused by physical items. So mental items are physical items. ;This section is also divisible into two …Read more
  •  1
    The Worm in the Cheese Leibniz, Consciousness and Matter
    Studia Leibnitiana 23 (1): 79-91. 1991.
    Leibniz argumentiert in der Monadologie, daß das Bewußtsein nicht auf rein mechanische und materielle Prozesse reduziert werden kann. Diesem wohlbekannten Argument wird bisweilen ein elementarer Trugschluß der Zusammensetzung vorgeworfen. Meiner Meinung nach hingegen weist dieses Argument eher auf ein grundlegendes Problem in unserem physikalischen Verständnis des menschlichen Geistes hin, einem Verständnis, das auch heute noch akzeptiert wird. Ich zeige jedoch weiterhin, daß Leibniz nicht erkan…Read more
  • Beyond theories: Cartwright and Hacking
    In James R. Brown (ed.), Philosophy of Science: The Key Thinkers, Continuum Books. pp. 213. 2012.
  •  103
    Classical Levels, Russellian Monism and the Implicate Order
    Foundations of Physics 43 (4): 548-567. 2013.
    Reception of the Bohm-Hiley interpretation of quantum mechanics has a curiously Janus faced quality. On the one hand, it is frequently derided as a conservative throwback to outdated classical patterns of thought. On the other hand, it is equally often taken to task for encouraging a wild quantum mysticism, often regarded as anti-scientific. I will argue that there are reasons for this reception, but that a proper appreciation of the dual scientific and philosophical aspects of the view reveals …Read more
  •  53
    Review of John Foster, A World for Us: The Case for Phenomenalistic Idealism (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (4). 2009.
  •  78
    Consciousness, value and functionalism
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 7. 2001.
    Charles Siewert presents a series of thought experiment based arguments against a wide range of current theories of phenomenal consciousness which I believe achieves a considerable measure of success. One topic which I think gets insufficient attention is the discussion of functionalism and I address this here. Before that I consider the intriguing issue, which is seldom considered but figures prominently at the close of Siewert's book, of the value of consciousness. In particular, I broach the …Read more
  •  403
    A brief history of the philosophical problem of consciousness
    In P. D. Zelazo, Morris Moscovitch & Evan Thompson (eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Consciousness, Cambridge University Press. pp. 9--33. 2007.
  •  156
    Theories of Consciousness provides an introduction to a variety of approaches to consciousness, questions the nature of consciousness, and contributes to current debates about whether a scientific understanding of consciousness is possible. While discussing key figures including Descartes, Fodor, Dennett and Chalmers, the book incorporates identity theories, representational theories, intentionality, externalism and new information-based theories
  •  23
    Is Nuclear Deterrence Paradoxical?
    Dialogue 23 (2): 187-198. 1984.
    A paradox is a situation in which two seemingly equally rational lines of thought lead to contradictory conclusions. A moral paradox is a situation where the employment of diverse moral principles, each of which is at least intuitively acceptable to roughly the same degree, leads to radically different moral assessments of one and the same action. In his “Some Paradoxes of Deterrence” Gregory Kavka argues that such moral paradoxes lurk in the concept of deterrence and further that the present wo…Read more
  •  196
    The spectacular success of the scientific enterprise over the last four hundred years has led to the promise of an all encompassing vision of the natural world. In this elegant picture, everything we observe is based upon just a few fundamental processes and entities. The almost infinite variety and complexity of the world is thus the product of emergence. But the concept of emergence is fraught with controversy and confusion. This book ponders the question of how emergence should be understood …Read more
  •  24
    The Problem of Consciousness by Colin McGinn (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 91 (6): 327-330. 1994.
  •  6
    Critical notice of Fred Dretske's Naturalizing the Mind
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27 (1): 83-109. 1997.