•  315
  •  33
    Ontologies on the Semantic Web
    Annual Review of Information Science and Technology 41 407-451. 2007.
    As an informational technology, the World Wide Web has enjoyed spectacular success. In just ten years it has transformed the way information is produced, stored, and shared in arenas as diverse as shopping, family photo albums, and high-level academic research. The “Semantic Web” was touted by its developers as equally revolutionary but has not yet achieved anything like the Web’s exponential uptake. This 17 000 word survey article explores why this might be so, from a perspective that bridges b…Read more
  •  107
    Real Law in Charles Peirce's Pragmaticism
    In Howard Sankey (ed.), Causation and Laws of Nature, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 125--142. 1999.
    How scholastic realism met the scientific method
  •  598
    Extension, Intension and Dormitive Virtue
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 35 (4). 1999.
    Would be fairer to call Peirce’s philosophy of language “extensionalist” or “intensionalist”? The extensionalisms of Carnap and Quine are examined, and Peirce’s view is found to be prima facie similar, except for his commitment to the importance of “hypostatic abstraction”. Rather than dismissing this form of abstraction (famously derided by Molière) as useless scholasticism, Peirce argues that it represents a crucial (though largely unnoticed) step in much working inference. This, it is argued,…Read more
  •  1224
    What is a Logical Diagram?
    In Sun-Joo Shin & Amirouche Moktefi (eds.), Visual Reasoning with Diagrams, Springer. pp. 1-18. 2013.
    Robert Brandom’s expressivism argues that not all semantic content may be made fully explicit. This view connects in interesting ways with recent movements in philosophy of mathematics and logic (e.g. Brown, Shin, Giaquinto) to take diagrams seriously - as more than a mere “heuristic aid” to proof, but either proofs themselves, or irreducible components of such. However what exactly is a diagram in logic? Does this constitute a semiotic natural kind? The paper will argue that such a natural kind…Read more
  •  142
    Paul Forster, "Peirce and the Threat of Nominalism" (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 51 (1): 137-8. 2013.
  •  738
    Charles S. Peirce’s semiotics uniquely divides signs into: i) symbols, which pick out their objects by arbitrary convention or habit, ii) indices, which pick out their objects by unmediated ‘pointing’, and iii) icons, which pick out their objects by resembling them (as Peirce put it: an icon’s parts are related in the same way that the objects represented by those parts are themselves related). Thus representing structure is one of the icon’s greatest strengths. It is argued that the implication…Read more
  •  371
    The Meaning of Meaning-Fallibilism
    Axiomathes 15 (2): 293-318. 2005.
    Much discussion of meaning by philosophers over the last 300 years has been predicated on a Cartesian first-person authority (i.e. “infallibilism”) with respect to what one’s terms mean. However this has problems making sense of the way the meanings of scientific terms develop, an increase in scientific knowledge over and above scientists’ ability to quantify over new entities. Although a recent conspicuous embrace of rigid designation has broken up traditional meaning-infallibilism to some exte…Read more
  •  129
    Gabriele Gava, "Peirce’s Account of Purposefulness: A Kantian Perspective" (review)
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 24 (2): 267-270. 2016.
  •  707
    Bill Gates is not a parking meter: Philosophical quality control in automated ontology building
    with Samuel Sarjant
    Proceedings of the Symposium on Computational Philosophy, AISB/IACAP World Congress 2012 (Birmingham, England, July 2-6). 2012.
    The somewhat old-fashioned concept of philosophical categories is revived and put to work in automated ontology building. We describe a project harvesting knowledge from Wikipedia’s category network in which the principled ontological structure of Cyc was leveraged to furnish an extra layer of accuracy-checking over and above more usual corrections which draw on automated measures of semantic relatedness.
  •  790
    The Problem of the Essential Icon
    American Philosophical Quarterly 45 (3): 207-232. 2008.
    Charles Peirce famously divided all signs into icons, indices and symbols. The past few decades have seen mainstream analytic philosophy broaden its traditional focus on symbols to recognise the so-called essential indexical. Can the moral now be extended to icons? Is there an “essential icon”? And if so, what exactly would be essential about it? It is argued that there is and it consists in logical form. Danielle Macbeth’s radical new “expressivist” interpretation of Frege’s logic and Charles P…Read more
  •  481
    Anne Freadman, "The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (4): 642-645. 2006.
    This book, officially a contribution to the subject area of Charles Peirce’s semiotics, deserves a wider readership, including philosophers. Its subject matter is what might be termed the great question of how signification is brought about (what Peirce called the ‘riddle of the Sphinx’, who in Emerson’s poem famously asked, ‘Who taught thee me to name?’), and also Peirce’s answer to the question (what Peirce himself called his ‘guess at the riddle’, and Freadman calls his ‘sign hypothesis’).
  •  489
    Richard Smyth, "Reading Peirce Reading" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 80 (3). 2002.
    Book Information Reading Peirce Reading. By Richard A. Smyth. Rowman and Littlefield. Maryland. 1997. Pp. ix + 327. Hardback, US$64.50. Paperback, US$24.95.
  •  441
    The word “hacker” has an interesting double meaning: one vastly more widespread connotation of technological mischief, even criminality, and an original meaning amongst the tech savvy as a term of highest approbation. Both meanings, however, share the idea that hackers possess a superior ability to manipulate technology according to their will (and, as with God, this superior ability to exercise will is a source of both mystifying admiration and fear). This book mainly concerns itself with the f…Read more
  •  19
    Integrating Cyc and Wikipedia: Folksonomy meets rigorously defined common-sense
    with Olena Medelyan
    Proceedings of Wikipedia and AI Workshop at the AAAI-08 Conference. Chicago, US, July 12 2008. 2008.
    Integration of ontologies begins with establishing mappings between their concept entries. We map categories from the largest manually-built ontology, Cyc, onto Wikipedia articles describing corresponding concepts. Our method draws both on Wikipedia’s rich but chaotic hyperlink structure and Cyc’s carefully defined taxonomic and common-sense knowledge. On 9,333 manual alignments by one person, we achieve an F-measure of 90%; on 100 alignments by six human subjects the average agreement of the me…Read more
  •  139
    Owen Holland, "Machine Consciousness" (review)
    Metapsychology Reviews Online 2004 (Sep): 1-5. 2004.
  •  217
    Huw Price
    In Graham Oppy & Nick Trakakis (eds.), A Companion to Philosophy in Australia and New Zealand, Monash University Epress. 2010.
    A review of the life and work of the Australian philosopher Huw Price
  •  627
    Much mainstream analytic epistemology is built around a sceptical treatment of modality which descends from Hume. The roots of this scepticism are argued to lie in Hume’s (nominalist) theory of perception, which is excavated, studied and compared with the very different (realist) theory of perception developed by Peirce. It is argued that Peirce’s theory not only enables a considerably more nuanced and effective epistemology, it also (unlike Hume’s theory) does justice to what happens when we ap…Read more
  •  39
    Peirce, Meaning, and the Semantic Web
    Semiotica 2013 (193): 119-143. 2013.
    This paper seeks an explanation for the challenges faced by Semantic Web developers in achieving their vision, compared to the staggering near-instantaneous success of the World Wide Web. To this end it contrasts two broad philosophical understandings of meaning and argues that the choice between them carries real consequences for how developers attempt to engineer the Semantic Web. The first is Rene Descartes’ ‘private’, static account of meaning (arguably dominant for the last 400 years in Wes…Read more
  •  372
    Catnesses
    In Stephen D. Hales (ed.), What Philosophy Can Tell You about Your Cat, Carus. 2008.
    An introduction to cat metaphysics
  •  78
    The Purpose of the Essential Indexical
    The Commens Working Papers: Preprints, Research Reports and Scientific Communications. 2015.
    This paper takes indexicality as a case-study for critical examination of the distinction between semantics and pragmatics as currently conceived in mainstream philosophy of language. Both a ‘pre-indexical’ and ‘post-indexical’ analytic formal semantics are examined and found wanting, and instead an argument is mounted for a ‘properly pragmatist pragmatics’, according to which we do not work out what signs mean in some abstract overall sense and then work out to what use they are being put; rath…Read more
  •  265
  •  856
    Charles Peirce's diagrammatic logic — the Existential Graphs — is presented as a tool for illuminating how we know necessity, in answer to Benacerraf's famous challenge that most ‘semantics for mathematics’ do not ‘fit an acceptable epistemology’. It is suggested that necessary reasoning is in essence a recognition that a certain structure has the particular structure that it has. This means that, contra Hume and his contemporary heirs, necessity is observable. One just needs to pay attention, n…Read more
  •  43
    Letting reality bite
    Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 44 (2): 208-212. 2008.
    Describes an experiment in teaching undergraduate epistemology, guided by Peirce’s pragmatic maxim.
  •  98
    Engineering philosophy
    International Journal of Machine Consciousness 2 (1): 45-50. 2010.
    A commentary on a current paper by Aaron Sloman. Sloman argues that in order to make progress in AI, consciousness, "should be replaced by more precise and varied architecture-based concepts better suited to specify what needs to be explained by scientific theories". This original vision of philosophical inquiry as mapping out 'design-spaces' for a contested concept seeks to achieve a holistic, synthetic understanding of what possibilities such spaces embody. It therefore does not reduce to eith…Read more
  •  169
    “Logic, Ethics and the Ethics of Logic”
    In T. Thellefsen B. Sorensen (ed.), Charles Sanders Peirce in His Own Words, . pp. 271-278. 2014.
    This piece explores the meaning of the following quote from Charles Peirce (1902), ". . . the main reason logic is unsettled is that thirteen different opinions are current as to the true aim of the science. Now this is not a logical difficulty, but an ethical difficulty; for ethics is the science of aims. Secondly, it is true that ethics has been, and always must be, a theatre of discussion for the reason that its study consists in the gradual development of a distinct recognition of a satisfac…Read more
  •  416
    Mining meaning from Wikipedia
    with David Milne, Medelyan Olena, and Witten Ian
    International Journal of Human-Computer Interactions 67 (9): 716-754. 2009.
    Wikipedia is a goldmine of information; not just for its many readers, but also for the growing community of researchers who recognize it as a resource of exceptional scale and utility. It represents a vast investment of manual effort and judgment: a huge, constantly evolving tapestry of concepts and relations that is being applied to a host of tasks. This article provides a comprehensive description of this work. It focuses on research that extracts and makes use of the concepts, relations, f…Read more
  •  220
    Peirce’s Reception in Australia and New Zealand
    European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy 6 (1). 2014.
    "Although I think it is far to say that in what natives of this part of the world call 'downunder,' Peirce is still a minority interest, appreciation of his work appears to be growing slowly but surely..."
  •  397
    Charles Peirce's Limit Concept of Truth
    Philosophy Compass 9 (3): 204-213. 2014.
    This entry explores Charles Peirce's account of truth in terms of the end or ‘limit’ of inquiry. This account is distinct from – and arguably more objectivist than – views of truth found in other pragmatists such as James and Rorty. The roots of the account in mathematical concepts is explored, and it is defended from objections that it is (i) incoherent, (ii) in its faith in convergence, too realist and (iii) in its ‘internal realism’, not realist enough