• Quassim Cassam, Self and World
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 6 (3): 448. 1998.
  •  6
    La perception interne et la critique du langage privé
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 130. 1998.
    Dans cet article, je me demande ce qui distingue la conscience 'externe' du monde (par exemple, la perception visuelle) et la conscience 'interne' du corps propre (par exemple, l'expérience de la douleur). Je rejette les théories analytiques récentes qui assimilent l'expérience de la douleur à une forme de perception externe, à savoir la perception d'un dommage physique relatif au corps du sujet. Mais je ne souscris pas pour autant à la thèse phénoménologique selon laquelle il y a un 'espace dou…Read more
  •  46
    Perceptual hysteresis as a marker of perceptual inflexibility in schizophrenia
    with Jean-Rémy Martin, Guillaume Dezecache, Daniel Pressnitzer, Philippe Nuss, Nicolas Bruno, Elisabeth Pacherie, and Nicolas Franck
    Consciousness and Cognition 30 (C): 62-72. 2014.
  •  34
    The framework of perception
    In Danièle Moyal-Sharrock, Volker Munz & Annalisa Coliva (eds.), Mind, Language and Action: Proceedings of the 36th International Wittgenstein Symposium, De Gruyter. pp. 347-356. 2015.
  • European Review of Philosophy, 2: Cognitive Dynamics (edited book)
    Center for the Study of Language and Inf. 1996.
  •  135
    Pictures in the Flesh Presence and Appearance in Pictorial Experience
    British Journal of Aesthetics 52 (4): 391-405. 2012.
    This essay explores the prospects of grounding an account of pictorial experience or ‘seeing-in’ on a theory of presence in ordinary perception. Even though worldly objects can be perceptually recognized in a picture, they do not feel present as when they are perceived face to face. I defend a dual view of perceptual phenomenology according to which the sense of presence is dissociated from the contents of perception. On the one hand, the sense of presence is best conceived as a non-sensory feel…Read more
  •  8
    L'esprit en Mouvement: Essai Sur la Dynamique Cognitive
    Center for the Study of Language and Information Publica Tion. 2001.
  •  239
    The Ontology of Perception: Bipolarity and Content
    Erkenntnis 48 (2-3): 153-169. 1998.
    The notion of perceptual content is commonly introduced in the analysis of perception. It stems from an analogy between perception and propositional attitudes. Both kinds of mental states, it is thought, have conditions of satisfaction. I try to show that on the most plausible account of perceptual content, it does not determine the conditions under which perceptual experience is veridical. Moreover, perceptual content must be bipolar (capable of being correct and capable of being incorrect), wh…Read more
  •  107
    IV—Aesthetic Experience as a Metacognitive Feeling? A Dual-Aspect View
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 116 (1): 69-88. 2016.
  •  166
    Seeds of self-knowledge: noetic feelings and metacognition
    In Michael Beran, Johannes Brandl, Josef Perner & Joëlle Proust (eds.), The Foundations of Metacognition, Oxford University Press. pp. 302--321. 2012.
  •  132
    Disjunctivism, Hallucination and Metacognition
    WIREs Cognitive Science 3 533-543. 2012.
    Perceptual experiences have been construed either as representational mental states—Representationalism—or as direct mental relations to the external world—Disjunctivism. Both conceptions are critical reactions to the so-called ‘Argument from Hallucination’, according to which perceptions cannot be about the external world, since they are subjectively indiscriminable from other, hallucinatory experiences, which are about sense-data ormind-dependent entities. Representationalism agrees that perce…Read more
  •  28
    Qu'est-ce que la perception?
    Librairie Philosophique Vrin. 2004.
    J. Dokic s'interroge sur le concept de perception : en quoi consiste-t-elle? comment fonctionne-t-elle?, etc. Cette analyse est suivie de deux textes commentés, l'un de George Berkeley "Les idées du haut et du bas", et "Le contenu non conceptuel" de John McDowell.
  •  298
    Margin for error and the transparency of knowledge
    Synthese 166 (1): 1-20. 2009.
    In chapter 5 of Knowledge and its Limits, T. Williamson formulates an argument against the principle (KK) of epistemic transparency, or luminosity of knowledge, namely “that if one knows something, then one knows that one knows it”. Williamson’s argument proceeds by reductio: from the description of a situation of approximate knowledge, he shows that a contradiction can be derived on the basis of principle (KK) and additional epistemic principles that he claims are better grounded. One of them i…Read more
  •  167
    Seeing Absence or Absence of Seeing?
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 2 (1): 117-125. 2013.
    Imagine that in entering a café, you are struck by the absence of Pierre, with whom you have an appointment. Or imagine that you realize that your keys are missing because they are not hanging from the usual ring-holder. What is the nature of these absence experiences? In this article, we discuss a recent view defended by Farennikova (2012) according to which we literally perceive absences of things in much the same way as we perceive present things. We criticize and reject the perceptual interp…Read more
  • Le corps en mouvement: les relations entre l'action, l'intention et le mouvement corporel
    Revue de Théologie Et de Philosophie 124 (3): 249-270. 1992.
  •  123
    Too much ado about belief
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6 (1-2): 185-200. 2007.
    Three commitments guide Dennett’s approach to the study of consciousness. First, an ontological commitment to materialist monism. Second, a methodological commitment to what he calls ‘heterophenomenology.’ Third, a ‘doxological’ commitment that can be expressed as the view that there is no room for a distinction between a subject’s beliefs about how things seem to her and what things actually seem to her, or, to put it otherwise, as the view that there is no room for a reality/appearance distinc…Read more
  •  149
    Our utterances are typically if not always "situated," in the sense that they are true or false relative to unarticulated parameters of the extra-linguistic context. The problem is to explain how these parameters are determined, given that nothing in the uttered sentences indicates them. It is tempting to claim that they must be determined at the level of thought or intention. However, as many philosophers have observed, thoughts themselves are no less situated than utterances. Unarticulated par…Read more