•  2
    Philosophers like asking questions about knowledge. What is it exactly? Why do we value it so much? And do we have any? Ideally they would like an account of the nature of knowledge that shows sceptical doubts about its existence to be unmotivated. Unfortunately two millenia of effort have not produced much in the way of agreed results.
  •  47
    Précis of Thinking about Consciousness
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (1): 143-143. 2002.
  •  48
    In this paper I want to explore the nature of phenomenal concepts by comparing them with perceptual concepts. Phenomenal concepts have been drawn to the attention of philosophers by recent debates in the philosophy of mind. Most obviously, their existence is demonstrated by Frank Jackson’s thought-experiment about Mary, the expert on the science of colour vision who has never had any colour experiences herself. It is widely agreed that, when Mary does first see something red, she acquires a new …Read more
  •  86
    Ideal types and empirical theories
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (2): 137-146. 1976.
  •  13
    It is widely supposed that the Everettian account of quantum mechanics has difficulties with probability. In this paper I shall argue that those who argue against the Everettian interpretation on this basis are employing a double standard. It is certainly true that there are philosophical puzzles about probability within the Everettian theory. But I shall show that orthodox metaphysics has even worse problems with probability than Everettianism. From this perspective, orthodox metaphysicians who…Read more
  •  124
    Realism, Ramsey sentences and the pessimistic meta-induction
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (4): 375-385. 2010.
    This paper defends scientific realism from the pessimistic meta-induction from past reference failure. It allows that a descriptive theory of reference implies that scientific terms characteristically fail of determinate reference. But it argues that a descriptive theory of reference also implies an equivalence between scientific theories and quantificational claims in the style of Ramsey. Since these quantificational claims do not use any of the referentially suspect scientific terms, they can …Read more
  •  69
    The Philosophical Insignificance of A Priori Knowledge
    In Michael J. Shaffer & Michael Veber (eds.), What Place for the a Priori?, Open Court. pp. 61. 2011.
  •  113
    The tyranny of common sense
    The Philosophers' Magazine 34 (34): 19-25. 2006.
    Sometimes I despair of my philosophical colleagues. They are so conservative. I don’t mean this in a political sense. In conventional party-political terms, most professional philosophers are probably well to the left of centre. As a group, they have a strong sense of fairness and little commitment to the social status quo. But this political openmindedness doesn’t normally carry over to their day jobs. When it comes to philosophical ideas, they are congenitally suspicious of intellectual innova…Read more
  •  74
    Naturalist Theories of Meaning
    In Ernest Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford: Oup. pp. 175-188. 2006.
    To begin with the former, representation is as familiar as it is puzzling. The English sentence ‘ Santiago is east of Sacramento’ represents the world as being a certain way. So does my belief that Santiago is east of Sacramento. In these examples, one item—a sentence or a belief—lays claim to something else, a state of affairs, which may be far removed in space and time. This is the phenomenon that naturalist theories of meaning aim to explain. How is it possible for one thing to stand for some…Read more
  •  252
    Editorial
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4): 787-788. 1998.
  •  92
    The Cultural Origins of Cognitive Adaptations
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 56 24-25. 2005.
    According to an influential view in contemporary cognitive science, many human cognitive capacities are innate. The primary support for this view comes from ‘poverty of stimulus’ arguments. In general outline, such arguments contrast the meagre informational input to cognitive development with its rich informational output. Consider the ease with which humans acquire languages, become facile at attributing psychological states (‘folk psychology’), gain knowledge of biological kinds (‘folk biolog…Read more
  •  4
    Review of J. Manninen and R. Tuomela: Essays on Explanation and Understanding (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (3): 304-310. 1978.
  •  19
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (1): 98-103. 1980.
  •  261
    Comments on Galen Strawson: Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 (10-11): 100-109. 2006.
    Galen Strawson (2006) thinks it is 'obviously' false that 'the terms of physics can fully capture the nature or essence of experience' (p. 4). He also describes this view as 'crazy' (p. 7). I think that he has been carried away by first impressions. It is certainly true that 'physicSalism', as he dubs this view, is strongly counterintuitive. But at the same time there are compelling arguments in its favour. I think that these arguments are sound and that the contrary intuitions are misbegotten. …Read more
  •  262
    Teleosemantics and indeterminacy
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1): 1-14. 1998.
    The aim of this paper is to defend the teleological theory of representation against an objection by Jerry Fodor. I shall argue that previous attempts to answer this objection fail to recognize the importance of belief-desire structure for the teleological theory of representation
  •  44
    Teleology and Mental States
    with William Charlton
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 65 (1): 17-54. 1991.
  •  202
    Why supervenience?
    Analysis 49 (2): 66-71. 1989.
  •  1
    Philosophical Naturalism (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 47 (189): 523-526. 1997.
  •  3
    REVIEW ARTICLE1: Correlations and Causes (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (3): 397-412. 1991.
  •  29
    My first university was in my home town, Durban, in the mid-1960s. I was doing a mathematics degree but most of my friends were doing arts subjects. Sartre and Marx were the thinkers of the moment and my friends would press their (mostly illegal) writings on me. Ideologically I was entirely sympathetic, but intellectually they didn’t do much for me—too obscure, too difficult, too dogmatic. In my final year I chanced on Ayer’s The Problem of Knowledge. It wasn’t exactly relevant to apartheid Sout…Read more
  •  10
    How does thought latch onto reality? Our minds have the ability to reach out and refer to items in the external world. I can think about the tree outside my study window, say, or about Margaret Thatcher, or about solar neutrinos. But how is the trick done? How can my thoughts refer to things beyond themselves? We tend to take the mind's referential powers for granted, but they are enormously difficult to explain. Whole philosophical systems have foundered on the problem of understanding mental r…Read more