•  64
    Western philosophy: an illustrated guide (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    What does it mean for someone to exist? What is truth? Are we free to choose to think or act? What is consciousness? Is human cloning justifiable? These are just some of the questions philosophers have attempted to answer, striking right at the heart of what it means to be human. This important new books shows that philosophy need not be dry or intimidating. Its highly original treatment, combining philosophical analysis, historical and biographical background and thought-provoking illustrations…Read more
  •  3
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (1): 304-310. 1980.
  •  350
    Causation is macroscopic but not irreducible
    In Sophie C. Gibb & Rögnvaldur Ingthorsson (eds.), Mental Causation and Ontology, Oxford University Press. pp. 126. 2013.
    In this paper I argue that causation is an essentially macroscopic phenomenon, and that mental causes are therefore capable of outcompeting their more specific physical realizers as causes of physical effects. But I also argue that any causes must be type-identical with physical properties, on pain of positing inexplicable physical conspiracies. I therefore allow macroscopic mental causation, but only when it is physically reducible
  • Science and Truth
    Ideas Y Valores 46 3-16. 1997.
  •  233
    In the Zone
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 73 175-196. 2013.
    On the Friday afternoon of the 3 rd test at Trent Bridge in 2001, the series was in the balance. The Australians had won the first two tests easily, but England now found themselves in a position of some strength. They had restricted Australia to a first-innings lead of just 5 runs, and had built a lead of 120 with six wickets in hand. Mark Ramprakash was in and had been batting steadily for well over an hour. Even though this Australian side was as strong as any in cricket history, England had …Read more
  •  96
    The virtues of randomization
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2): 437-450. 1994.
    Peter Urbach has argued, on Bayesian grounds, that experimental randomization serves no useful purpose in testing causal hypothesis. I maintain that he fails to distinguish general issues of statistical inference from specific problems involved in identifying causes. I concede the general Bayesian thesis that random sampling is inessential to sound statistical inference. But experimental randomization is a different matter, and often plays an essential role in our route to causal conclusions.
  •  117
    Causal asymmetry
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (3): 273-289. 1985.
  • HARRISON, B. "An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language" (review)
    Mind 91 (n/a): 610. 1982.
  •  392
    The poverty of analysis
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83 (1): 1-30. 2009.
    I argue that philosophy is like science in three interesting and non-obvious ways. First, the claims made by philosophy are synthetic, not analytic: philosophical claims, just like scientific claims, are not guaranteed by the structure of the concepts they involve. Second, philosophical knowledge is a posteriori, not a priori: the claims established by philosophers depend on the same kind of empirical support as scientific theories. And finally, the central questions of philosophy concern actual…Read more
  •  68
    Three scenes and a moral
    The Philosophers' Magazine 38 (38): 63-64. 2007.
  •  41
    Probability and normativity
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3): 484-485. 1989.
  •  12
    Who would have thought it? Poker has become a mass-audience spectator sport. Names like Chris ‘Jesus’ Ferguson, Phil ‘Unabomber’ Laak, and Dave ‘The Devilfish’ Ulliott may not be familiar to all readers of the TLS, but on any normal night you can see these top poker professionals on the nether reaches of the satellite channels, as they bluff and bully their way to pots worth hundreds of thousands of dollars. Like their counterparts in tennis and golf, they tour the world, playing in lucrative to…Read more
  •  19
    Replies to commentators (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (1). 2005.
  •  38
    Explanatory gaps and dualist intuitions
    In Lawrence Weiskrantz & Martin Davies (eds.), Frontiers of consciousness, Oxford University Press. pp. 2008--55. 2008.
    I agree with nearly everything Martin Davies says. He has written an elegant and highly informative analysis of recent philosophical debates about the mind–brain relation. I particularly enjoyed Davies’ discussion of B.A. Farrell, his precursor in the Oxford Wilde Readership (now Professorship) in Mental Philosophy. It is intriguing to see how closely Farrell anticipated many of the moves made by more recent ‘type-A’ physicalists who seek to show that, upon analysis, claims about conscious state…Read more
  •  44
    Why is there a cognitive gulf between other animals and humans? Current fashion favours our greater understanding of Theory of Mind as an answer, and Language is another obvious candidate. But I think that analysis of the evolution of means-end cognitive mechanisms suggests that there may be a further significant difference: where animals will only perform those means which they (or their ancestors) have previously used as a route to some end, humans can employ observation to learn that some nov…Read more
  •  50
    Introduction: Prospects and problems for teleosemantics
    with Graham Macdonald
    In Graham Macdonald & David Papineau (eds.), Teleosemantics: New Philosophical Essays, Oxford University Press. pp. 1--22. 2006.
  •  6
    Review: Correlations and Causes (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (3). 1991.
  • Theory and Meaning
    Mind 92 (368): 618-622. 1983.
  •  404
    I shall begin with the "anti-psychiatry" view that the lack of a physical basis excludes many familiar mental disorders from the category of "illness". My response to this argument will be that anti-psychiatrists are probably right to hold that most mental disorders do not involve any physical disorder, but that they are wrong to conclude from this that these mental disorders are not illnesses
  •  32
    X*—Is Epistemology Dead?
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 82 (1): 129-142. 1982.
    David Papineau; X*—Is Epistemology Dead?, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 82, Issue 1, 1 June 1982, Pages 129–142, https://doi.org/10.1093/arist.
  •  80
    Review article: Correlations and causes
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (3): 397-412. 1991.
  •  130
    Could there be a science of consciousness?
    Philosophical Issues 13 (1): 205-20. 2003.
    Article
  •  28
    Salmon, Statistics, and Backwards Causation
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1978 302-313. 1978.
    In order to explain why falling barometers don't cause rain, a "no-eclipsing" requirement needs to be added to the regularity account of causation. This refinement of the regularity account allows us to see how conclusions about deterministic causes can be based on statistical premises, and thus indicates a criticism of Wesley Salmon 's "statistical relevance" account of causation. The refinement also casts some light on the problem of backwards causation
  •  228
    Kripke's proof is ad hominem not two-dimensional
    Philosophical Perspectives 21 (1). 2007.
    Identity theorists make claims like ‘pain = C-fibre stimulation’. These claims must be necessary if true, given that terms like ‘pain’ and ‘C-fibre stimulation’ are rigid. Yet there is no doubt that such claims appear contingent. It certainly seems that there could have been C-fibre stimulation without pains or vice versa. So identity theorists owe us an explanation of why such claims should appear contingent if they are in fact necessary.