• Theory and Meaning
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33 (1): 101-104. 1982.
  •  7
    Teleology and Mental States
    with William Charlton
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 65 (1): 17-54. 1991.
  • Reality and Representation
    Mind 97 (388): 629-632. 1988.
  • Theory and Meaning
    Philosophy of Science 48 (3): 500-502. 1981.
  •  6
    Foul play
    The Philosophers' Magazine 67 35-39. 2014.
  •  71
    Can we be harmed after we are dead?
    Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 18 (5): 1091-1094. 2012.
  •  30
  •  27
    Nature and nurture
    Journal of Medical Ethics 8 (2): 96-99. 1982.
  •  442
    Mind the gap
    Philosophical Perspectives 12 373-89. 1998.
    On the first page of The Problem of Consciousness , Colin McGinn asks "How is it possible for conscious states to depend on brain states? How can technicolour phenomenology arise from soggy grey matter?" Many philosophers feel that questions like these pose an unanswerable challenge to physicalism. They argue that there is no way of bridging the "explanatory gap" between the material brain and the lived world of conscious experience , and that physicalism about the mind can therefore provide no …Read more
  •  150
    Reply to Kirk and Melnyk
    SWIF Philosophy of Mind 4 (1). 2003.
    I am lucky to have two such penetrating commentators as Robert Kirk and Andrew Melnyk. It is also fortunate that they come at me from different directions, and so cover different aspects of my book. Robert Kirk has doubts about the overall structure of my enterprise, and in particular about my central commitment to a distinctive species of phenomenal concepts. Andrew Melnyk, by contrast, offers no objections to my general brand of materialism. Instead he focuses specifically on my discussion of …Read more
  •  324
    Theories of consciousness
    In Quentin Smith & Aleksandar Jokić (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Essays, Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 353. 2003.
    My target in this paper is "theories of consciousness". There are many theories of consciousness around, and my view is that they are all misconceived. Consciousness is not a normal scientific subject, and needs handling with special care. It is foolhardy to jump straight in and start building a theory, as if consciousness were just like electricity or chemical valency. We will do much better to reflect explicitly on our methodology first. When we do this, we will see that theories of consciousn…Read more
  •  5
    Introducing Consciousness
    Totem Books. 2000.
    This title is now available in a new format. Refer to Consciousness: A Graphic Guide 9781848311718.
  •  12
    Who would have thought it? Poker has become a mass-audience spectator sport. Names like Chris ‘Jesus’ Ferguson, Phil ‘Unabomber’ Laak, and Dave ‘The Devilfish’ Ulliott may not be familiar to all readers of the TLS, but on any normal night you can see these top poker professionals on the nether reaches of the satellite channels, as they bluff and bully their way to pots worth hundreds of thousands of dollars. Like their counterparts in tennis and golf, they tour the world, playing in lucrative to…Read more
  •  19
    Replies to commentators (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (1). 2005.
  • HARRISON, B. "An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language" (review)
    Mind 91 (n/a): 610. 1982.
  •  394
    The poverty of analysis
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83 (1): 1-30. 2009.
    I argue that philosophy is like science in three interesting and non-obvious ways. First, the claims made by philosophy are synthetic, not analytic: philosophical claims, just like scientific claims, are not guaranteed by the structure of the concepts they involve. Second, philosophical knowledge is a posteriori, not a priori: the claims established by philosophers depend on the same kind of empirical support as scientific theories. And finally, the central questions of philosophy concern actual…Read more
  •  41
    Probability and normativity
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3): 484-485. 1989.
  •  50
    Introduction: Prospects and problems for teleosemantics
    with Graham Macdonald
    In Graham Macdonald & David Papineau (eds.), Teleosemantics: New Philo-sophical Essays, Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 1--22. 2006.
  •  6
    Review: Correlations and Causes (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (3). 1991.
  •  209
    By way of an example, Lewis imagines your being invited to join Schrödinger’s cat in its box for an hour. This box will either fill up with deadly poison fumes or not, depending on whether or not some radioactive atom decays, the probability of decay within an hour being 50%. The invitation is accompanied with some further incentive to comply (Lewis sets it up so there is a significant chance of some pretty bad but not life-threatening punishment if you don’t get in the box). Lewis argues that t…Read more
  •  38
    Explanatory gaps and dualist intuitions
    In Lawrence Weiskrantz & Martin Davies (eds.), Frontiers of consciousness, Oxford University Press. pp. 2008--55. 2008.
    I agree with nearly everything Martin Davies says. He has written an elegant and highly informative analysis of recent philosophical debates about the mind–brain relation. I particularly enjoyed Davies’ discussion of B.A. Farrell, his precursor in the Oxford Wilde Readership (now Professorship) in Mental Philosophy. It is intriguing to see how closely Farrell anticipated many of the moves made by more recent ‘type-A’ physicalists who seek to show that, upon analysis, claims about conscious state…Read more
  •  46
    Why is there a cognitive gulf between other animals and humans? Current fashion favours our greater understanding of Theory of Mind as an answer, and Language is another obvious candidate. But I think that analysis of the evolution of means-end cognitive mechanisms suggests that there may be a further significant difference: where animals will only perform those means which they (or their ancestors) have previously used as a route to some end, humans can employ observation to learn that some nov…Read more
  •  81
    Review article: Correlations and causes
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (3): 397-412. 1991.
  •  107
    Imagine you are faced with a quantum mechanical device which will display either H or T when it is operated. You know that the single-case probability, or chance, of H is 0.8, and the chance of T is 0.2.
  •  131
    Could there be a science of consciousness?
    Philosophical Issues 13 (1): 205-20. 2003.
    Article