•  5
    Introducing Consciousness
    Totem Books. 2000.
    This title is now available in a new format. Refer to Consciousness: A Graphic Guide 9781848311718.
  •  4
    Conditionals
    Philosophical Quarterly 39 (57): 493. 1989.
  •  18
    The empirical evidence often justifies belief in scientific theories. For instance, the great wealth of chemical and other relevant data leaves us with no real alternative to believing that matter is made of atoms. Similarly, the natural history of past and present organisms makes it irrational to deny that life on earth has evolved from a common ancestry. Again, the character and epidemiology of infectious diseases effectively establishes that they are caused by microbes. Peter Lipton did much …Read more
  •  147
    This book is designed to explain the technical ideas that are taken for granted in much contemporary philosophical writing. Notions like "denumerability," "modal scope distinction," "Bayesian conditionalization," and "logical completeness" are usually only elucidated deep within difficult specialist texts. By offering simple explanations that by-pass much irrelevant and boring detail, Philosophical Devices is able to cover a wealth of material that is normally only available to specialists. The …Read more
  •  107
    Imagine you are faced with a quantum mechanical device which will display either H or T when it is operated. You know that the single-case probability, or chance, of H is 0.8, and the chance of T is 0.2.
  •  30
    Reuniting (scene) phenomenology with (scene) access
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 521-521. 2007.
    Block shows that we can consciously see a scene without being able to identify all the individual items in it. But in itself this fails to drive a wedge between phenomenology and access. Once we distinguish scene phenomenology from item phenomenology, the link between phenomenology and access is restored
  •  119
    The philosophy of science (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1996.
    The newest addition to the successful Oxford Readings in Philosophy series, this collection contains the most important contributions to the recent debate on the philosophy of science. The contributors crystallize the often heated arguments of the last two decades, assessing the skeptical attitudes within philosophy of science and the counter-challenges of the scientific realists. Contributors include Nancy Cartwright, Brian Ellis, Arthur Fine, Clark Glymour, Larry Laudan, Peter Lipton, Alan Mus…Read more
  •  207
    Theory-dependent terms
    Philosophy of Science 63 (1): 1-20. 1996.
    The main puzzle about theoretical definitions is that nothing seems to decide which assumptions contribute to such definitions and which do not. I argue that theoretical definitions are indeed imprecise, but that this does not normally matter, since the definitional imprecision does not normally produce indeterminacy of referential value. Sometimes, however, the definitional imprecision is less benign, and does generate referential indeterminacy. In these special cases, but not otherwise, it is …Read more
  •  1
    Arguments for supervenience and physical realization
    In Elias E. Savellos & Ümit D. Yalçin (eds.), Supervenience: New Essays, Cambridge University Press. 1995.
  •  9
    Review: Conditionals (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 39 (157). 1989.
  • Editorial
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4): 531-531. 1998.
  •  1
    Teleosemántíca e Indeterminación
    Ideas Y Valores 47 (106): 136-159. 1998.
  •  25
    A reduction of causation to probabilities would be a great achievement, if it were possible.  In this paper I want to defend this reductionist ambition against some recent criticisms from Gurol Irzik (1996) and Dan Hausman (1998). In particular, I want to show that the reductionist programme can be absolved of a vice which is widely thought to disable it--the vice of infidelity
  •  44
    Tainted Cash?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 3 (3): 26-27. 1998.
  •  3
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33 (4): 444-448. 1982.
  •  5
    Content, reasons and knowledge
    Philosophical Books 28 (1): 1-9. 1987.
  •  47
    Theory and meaning
    Oxford University Press. 1979.
    This book is concerned with those aspects of the theory of meaning for scientific terms that are relevant to questions about the evaluation of scientific theories. The contemporary debate about theory choice in science is normally presented as a conflict between two sets of ideas. On the one hand are notions of objectivity, realism, rationality, and progress in science. On the other is the view that meanings depend on theory, with associated claims about the theory dependence of observation, the…Read more
  •  72
    Must a physicalist be a microphysicalist?
    In Jakob Hohwy & Jesper Kallestrup (eds.), Being Reduced: New Essays on Reduction, Explanation, and Causation, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    This chapter challenges the entailment from physicalism to microphysicalism — the view that all facts metaphysically supervene on the microphysical facts. It observes that physicalists can avoid microphysicalism by rejecting physical microscopism. Humean supervenience is a strong version of microphysicalism, and it is false if a non-Humean view of laws is true. But such a view is consistent with physicalism. A weaker form of microphysicalism adds microphysical non-Humean laws to get a broader mi…Read more
  •  37
    Scientific realism without reference
    with Pierre Cruse
    In Michele Marsonet (ed.), The Problem of Realism, Ashgate. pp. 174--189. 2002.
  •  13
    Causes and mixed probabilities
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (1). 1990.
    Abstract In Section 1 I examine the use of probabilistic data to establish causal conclusions in non?experimental research. In Section 2 I show that the probabilities involved in such research are inhomogeneous ?mixed? probabilities. Section 3 then argues that such mixed probabilities are responsible for the way common causes screen off correlations between their joint effects. Section 4 concludes that mixed probabilities are therefore crucial for the nature of the causal relation itself
  •  8
    Response to Ehring’s ’Papineau on Causal Asymmetry’
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (4): 521-525. 1988.
  •  67
    Western philosophy: an illustrated guide (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    What does it mean for someone to exist? What is truth? Are we free to choose to think or act? What is consciousness? Is human cloning justifiable? These are just some of the questions philosophers have attempted to answer, striking right at the heart of what it means to be human. This important new books shows that philosophy need not be dry or intimidating. Its highly original treatment, combining philosophical analysis, historical and biographical background and thought-provoking illustrations…Read more
  •  298
    Since the publication of Elga's seminal paper in 2000, the Sleeping Beauty paradox has been the source of much discussion, particularly in this journal. Over the past few decades the Everettian interpretation of quantum mechanics 1 has also been much debated. There is an interesting connection between the way these two topics raise issues about subjective probability assignments.This connection is often alluded to, but as far as we know Peter J. Lewis's ‘Quantum Sleeping Beauty’ is the first att…Read more
  •  104
    Response to Ehring's 'papineau on causal asymmetry'
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (4): 521-525. 1988.