•  117
    The philosophy of science (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1996.
    The newest addition to the successful Oxford Readings in Philosophy series, this collection contains the most important contributions to the recent debate on the philosophy of science. The contributors crystallize the often heated arguments of the last two decades, assessing the skeptical attitudes within philosophy of science and the counter-challenges of the scientific realists. Contributors include Nancy Cartwright, Brian Ellis, Arthur Fine, Clark Glymour, Larry Laudan, Peter Lipton, Alan Mus…Read more
  •  117
    Causal asymmetry
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (3): 273-289. 1985.
  •  113
    The tyranny of common sense
    The Philosophers' Magazine 34 (34): 19-25. 2006.
    Sometimes I despair of my philosophical colleagues. They are so conservative. I don’t mean this in a political sense. In conventional party-political terms, most professional philosophers are probably well to the left of centre. As a group, they have a strong sense of fairness and little commitment to the social status quo. But this political openmindedness doesn’t normally carry over to their day jobs. When it comes to philosophical ideas, they are congenitally suspicious of intellectual innova…Read more
  •  107
    Imagine you are faced with a quantum mechanical device which will display either H or T when it is operated. You know that the single-case probability, or chance, of H is 0.8, and the chance of T is 0.2.
  •  107
    Discussion of Christopher Peacocke’s A Study of Concepts (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 425. 1996.
    Christopher Peacocke’s A Study of Concepts is a dense and rewarding work. Each chapter raises many issues for discussion. I know three different people who are writing reviews of the volume. It testifies to the depth of Peacocke’s book that each reviewer is focusing on a quite different set of topics.
  •  104
    What is x-phi good for?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 52 (52): 83-88. 2011.
    When philosophers study knowledge, consciousness, free will, moral value, and so on, their first concern is with these things themselves, rather than with what people think about them. So why exactly is it so important to philosophy to discover experimentally that people differ in their views on these matters? We wouldn’t expect physicists to throw up their hands in excitement just because somebody shows that different cultures have different views about the origin of the universe
  •  103
    Response to Chalmers' 'The Meta-Problem of Consciousness'
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 26 (9-10): 173-181. 2019.
    I am glad that David Chalmers has now come round to the view that explaining the 'problem intuitions' about consciousness is the key to a satisfactory philosophical account of the topic. I find it surprising, however, given his previous writings, that Chalmers does not simply attribute these intuitions to the conceptual gap between physical and phenomenal facts. Still, it is good that he doesn't, given that this was always a highly implausible account of the problem intuitions. Unfortunately, la…Read more
  •  101
    Response to Ehring's 'papineau on causal asymmetry'
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (4): 521-525. 1988.
  •  96
    The virtues of randomization
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2): 437-450. 1994.
    Peter Urbach has argued, on Bayesian grounds, that experimental randomization serves no useful purpose in testing causal hypothesis. I maintain that he fails to distinguish general issues of statistical inference from specific problems involved in identifying causes. I concede the general Bayesian thesis that random sampling is inessential to sound statistical inference. But experimental randomization is a different matter, and often plays an essential role in our route to causal conclusions.
  •  93
    8 The evolution of knowledge
    In Peter Carruthers & A. Chamberlain (eds.), Evolution and the Human Mind: Modularity, Language and Meta-Cognition, Cambridge University Press. pp. 170. 2000.
  •  91
    The Cultural Origins of Cognitive Adaptations
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 56 24-25. 2005.
    According to an influential view in contemporary cognitive science, many human cognitive capacities are innate. The primary support for this view comes from ‘poverty of stimulus’ arguments. In general outline, such arguments contrast the meagre informational input to cognitive development with its rich informational output. Consider the ease with which humans acquire languages, become facile at attributing psychological states (‘folk psychology’), gain knowledge of biological kinds (‘folk biolog…Read more
  •  91
    Is Representation Rife?
    Ratio 16 (2): 107-123. 2003.
    This paper applies a teleosemantic perspective to the question of whether there is genuine representation outside the familiar realm of belief‐desire psychology. I first explain how teleosemantics accounts for the representational powers of beliefs and desires themselves. I then ask whether biological states which are simpler than beliefs and desires can also have representational powers. My conclusion is that such biologically simple states can be ascribed representational contents, but only in…Read more
  •  90
    Head hurters
    with Richard Ashcroft, Stephen Burwood, J. B. Kennedy, and Bart Schultz
    The Philosophers' Magazine 30 (30): 57-61. 2005.
  •  86
    Ideal types and empirical theories
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (2): 137-146. 1976.
  •  85
    Ramsey-Lewis Is Better than Mackie
    Analysis 48 (2). 1988.
  •  82
    The British difference
    with Simon Blackburn, A. C. Grayling, Ted Honderich, and Richard Norman
    The Philosophers' Magazine 18 (18): 37-38. 2002.
  •  82
    Doubtful intuitions
    Mind and Language 11 (1): 130-32. 1996.
  •  80
    Review article: Correlations and causes
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (3): 397-412. 1991.
  •  77
    The vis viva controversy: Do meanings matter?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 8 (2): 111-142. 1977.
  •  74
    Naturalist Theories of Meaning
    In Ernest Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford: Oup. pp. 175-188. 2006.
    To begin with the former, representation is as familiar as it is puzzling. The English sentence ‘ Santiago is east of Sacramento’ represents the world as being a certain way. So does my belief that Santiago is east of Sacramento. In these examples, one item—a sentence or a belief—lays claim to something else, a state of affairs, which may be far removed in space and time. This is the phenomenon that naturalist theories of meaning aim to explain. How is it possible for one thing to stand for some…Read more
  •  70
    Can we be harmed after we are dead?
    Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice 18 (5): 1091-1094. 2012.
  •  69
    Precis of Philosophical NaturalismPhilosophical Naturalism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (3): 657. 1996.
    This precis explains that _Philosophical naturalism contains three parts. Part I examines arguments for physicalism and maintains I) that all causally relevant special science properties must be realized by physical ones, and II) that all special science laws must reduce to physical ones, apart from the significant category of special laws that result from selection processes. Part II defends a teleological theory of representation and an identity theory of consciousness. Part III defends reliab…Read more
  •  69
    The Philosophical Insignificance of A Priori Knowledge
    In Michael J. Shaffer & Michael Veber (eds.), What Place for the a Priori?, Open Court. pp. 61. 2011.
  •  68
    Round Table: Science vs Philosophy?
    with Mary Midgley, Raymond Tallis, Lewis Wolpert, and Anja Steinbauer
    Philosophy Now 27 34-38. 2000.
  •  68
    Three scenes and a moral
    The Philosophers' Magazine 38 (38): 63-64. 2007.
  •  68
    Swampman, teleosemantics and kind essences
    Synthese 200 (6): 1-19. 2022.
    One powerful and influential approach to mental representation analyses representation in terms of biological functions, and biological functions in terms of histories of natural selection. This “teleosemantic” package, however, faces a familiar challenge. Surely representation depends only on the present-day structures of cognitive systems, and not on their historical provenance. “Swampman” drives the point home. Suppose a bolt of lightning creates an intrinsic duplicate of a human being in a s…Read more
  •  65
    Teleology and Mental States
    with William Charlton
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 65 (1): 17-54. 1991.
  •  65
    David Papineau presents a controversial view of human reason, portraying it as a normal part of the natural world, and drawing on the empirical sciences to illuminate its workings. In these six interconnected essays he discusses both theoretical and practical rationality, and shows how evolutionary theory, decision theory, and quantum mechanics offer fresh approaches to some long-standing problems