•  323
    Theories of consciousness
    In Quentin Smith & Aleksandar Jokic (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Essays, Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 353. 2003.
    My target in this paper is "theories of consciousness". There are many theories of consciousness around, and my view is that they are all misconceived. Consciousness is not a normal scientific subject, and needs handling with special care. It is foolhardy to jump straight in and start building a theory, as if consciousness were just like electricity or chemical valency. We will do much better to reflect explicitly on our methodology first. When we do this, we will see that theories of consciousn…Read more
  •  1
  •  146
    This book is designed to explain the technical ideas that are taken for granted in much contemporary philosophical writing. Notions like "denumerability," "modal scope distinction," "Bayesian conditionalization," and "logical completeness" are usually only elucidated deep within difficult specialist texts. By offering simple explanations that by-pass much irrelevant and boring detail, Philosophical Devices is able to cover a wealth of material that is normally only available to specialists. The …Read more
  •  4
    Conditionals
    Philosophical Quarterly 39 (57): 493. 1989.
  •  18
    The empirical evidence often justifies belief in scientific theories. For instance, the great wealth of chemical and other relevant data leaves us with no real alternative to believing that matter is made of atoms. Similarly, the natural history of past and present organisms makes it irrational to deny that life on earth has evolved from a common ancestry. Again, the character and epidemiology of infectious diseases effectively establishes that they are caused by microbes. Peter Lipton did much …Read more
  •  1
    Arguments for supervenience and physical realization
    In Elias E. Savellos & U. Yalcin (eds.), Supervenience: New Essays, Cambridge University Press. 1995.
  •  29
    Reuniting (scene) phenomenology with (scene) access
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 521-521. 2007.
    Block shows that we can consciously see a scene without being able to identify all the individual items in it. But in itself this fails to drive a wedge between phenomenology and access. Once we distinguish scene phenomenology from item phenomenology, the link between phenomenology and access is restored
  •  117
    The philosophy of science (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1996.
    The newest addition to the successful Oxford Readings in Philosophy series, this collection contains the most important contributions to the recent debate on the philosophy of science. The contributors crystallize the often heated arguments of the last two decades, assessing the skeptical attitudes within philosophy of science and the counter-challenges of the scientific realists. Contributors include Nancy Cartwright, Brian Ellis, Arthur Fine, Clark Glymour, Larry Laudan, Peter Lipton, Alan Mus…Read more
  •  42
    Tainted Cash?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 3 (3): 26-27. 1998.
  •  9
    Review: Conditionals (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 39 (157). 1989.
  • Editorial
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49 (4): 531-531. 1998.
  •  1
    Teleosemántíca e Indeterminación
    Ideas Y Valores 47 (106): 136-159. 1998.
  •  650
    What Exactly is the Explanatory Gap?
    Philosophia 39 (1): 5-19. 2011.
    It is widely agreed among contemporary philosophers of mind that science leaves us with an ‘explanatory gap’—that even after we know everything that science can tell us about the conscious mind and the brain, their relationship still remains mysterious. I argue that this agreed view is quite mistaken. The feeling of a ‘explanatory gap’ arises only because we cannot stop ourselves thinking about the mind–brain relation in a dualist way
  •  25
    A reduction of causation to probabilities would be a great achievement, if it were possible.  In this paper I want to defend this reductionist ambition against some recent criticisms from Gurol Irzik (1996) and Dan Hausman (1998). In particular, I want to show that the reductionist programme can be absolved of a vice which is widely thought to disable it--the vice of infidelity
  •  3
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33 (4): 444-448. 1982.
  •  5
    Content, reasons and knowledge
    Philosophical Books 28 (1): 1-9. 1987.
  •  45
    Theory and meaning
    Oxford University Press. 1979.
    This book is concerned with those aspects of the theory of meaning for scientific terms that are relevant to questions about the evaluation of scientific theories. The contemporary debate about theory choice in science is normally presented as a conflict between two sets of ideas. On the one hand are notions of objectivity, realism, rationality, and progress in science. On the other is the view that meanings depend on theory, with associated claims about the theory dependence of observation, the…Read more
  •  20
    The tyranny of common sense
    The Philosophers' Magazine 34 19-25. 2006.
  •  64
    Must a physicalist be a microphysicalist?
    In Jakob Hohwy & Jesper Kallestrup (eds.), Being Reduced: New Essays on Reduction, Explanation, and Causation, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    This chapter challenges the entailment from physicalism to microphysicalism — the view that all facts metaphysically supervene on the microphysical facts. It observes that physicalists can avoid microphysicalism by rejecting physical microscopism. Humean supervenience is a strong version of microphysicalism, and it is false if a non-Humean view of laws is true. But such a view is consistent with physicalism. A weaker form of microphysicalism adds microphysical non-Humean laws to get a broader mi…Read more
  •  37
    Scientific realism without reference
    with Pierre Cruse
    In Michele Marsonet (ed.), The Problem of Realism, Ashgate. pp. 174--189. 2002.
  •  8
    Response to Ehring’s ’Papineau on Causal Asymmetry’
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (4): 521-525. 1988.
  •  13
    Causes and mixed probabilities
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 4 (1). 1990.
    Abstract In Section 1 I examine the use of probabilistic data to establish causal conclusions in non?experimental research. In Section 2 I show that the probabilities involved in such research are inhomogeneous ?mixed? probabilities. Section 3 then argues that such mixed probabilities are responsible for the way common causes screen off correlations between their joint effects. Section 4 concludes that mixed probabilities are therefore crucial for the nature of the causal relation itself
  •  206
    Physicalism, consciousness and the antipathetic fallacy
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (2): 169-83. 1993.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  289
    Since the publication of Elga's seminal paper in 2000, the Sleeping Beauty paradox has been the source of much discussion, particularly in this journal. Over the past few decades the Everettian interpretation of quantum mechanics 1 has also been much debated. There is an interesting connection between the way these two topics raise issues about subjective probability assignments.This connection is often alluded to, but as far as we know Peter J. Lewis's ‘Quantum Sleeping Beauty’ is the first att…Read more
  •  101
    Response to Ehring's 'papineau on causal asymmetry'
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (4): 521-525. 1988.