•  89
    Hope as a Primitive Mental State
    Ratio 28 (2): 207-222. 2015.
    We criticize attempts to define hope in terms of other psychological states and argue that hope is a primitive mental state whose nature can be illuminated by specifying key aspects of its functional profile
  • Review of M. Stepanians: Gottlob Frege zur Einführung (review)
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 57 (3). 2003.
  •  148
    Unsaturatedness: Wittgenstein's challenge, Frege's answer
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109 (1pt1): 61-82. 2009.
    Frege holds the distinction between complete (saturated) and incomplete (unsaturated) things to be a basic distinction of logic. Many disagree. In this paper I will argue that one can defend Frege's distinction against criticism if one takes, inspired by Frege, a wh -question to be the paradigm incomplete expression.
  •  38
    From Mental Holism to the Soul and Back
    The Monist 100 (1): 133-154. 2017.
    In his Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt Brentano proposed a view of consciousness that neither has room nor need for a subject of mental acts, a soul. Later he changed his mind: there is a soul that appears in consciousness. In this paper I will argue that Brentano’s change of view is not justified. The subjectless view of consciousness can be defended against Brentano’s argument and it is superior to its predecessor.
  •  97
    Sense-only-signs: Frege on fictional proper names
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 82 (1): 375-400. 2011.
    I explore Frege's thesis that fictional proper names are supposed to have only sense and no reference. How can one make this thesis compatible with Frege's view that sense determines reference? By holding that fictional proper names are introduced in a particular kind of speech act. Or so I argue.
  •  78
    Arguments for and against the existence of demonstrative concepts of shades and shapes turn on the assumption that demonstrative concepts must be recognitional capacities. The standard argument for this assumption is based on the widely held view that concepts are those constituents of propositional attitudes that account for an attitude's inferential potential. Only if demonstrative concepts of shades are recognitional capacities, the standard argument goes, can they account for the inferential…Read more
  •  70
    Rigidity and De Jure Rigidity
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 17 (1): 45-59. 1998.
    Most discussions of Kripke's Naming and Necessity focus either on Kripke's so-called "historical theory of reference" or his thesis that names are rigid designators. But in response to problems of the rigidity thesis Kripke later points out that his thesis about proper names is a stronger one: proper names are de jure rigid. This sets the agenda for my paper. Certain problems raised for Kripke's view show that the notion of de jure rigidity is in need of clarification. I will try to clarify the …Read more
  •  109
    Brentano on the dual relation of the mental
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 12 (3): 465-483. 2013.
    Brentano held that every mental phenomenon has an object and is conscious (the dual relation thesis). The dual relation thesis faces a number of well-known problems. The paper explores how Brentano tried to overcome these problems. In considering Brentano's responses, the paper sheds light on Brentano's theory of judgement that underpins his philosophy of mind
  •  1
    Are Particulars or States of Affairs Given in
    In M. Reicher (ed.), States of Affairs, Ontos Verlag. pp. 30--129. 2009.
    The paper argues that the basic objects of perception are particulars, tropes in particular. It defends this view by proposing a response to the objection that we cannot perceive particulars without perceiving that it is so-and-so.
  •  94
    Is 'no' a force-indicator? No!
    Analysis 71 (3): 448-456. 2011.
  •  47
    What Brentano criticizes in Reid
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (1). 2004.
    No abstract
  •  89
    According to Frege, we need a criterion for recognising when different sentences express the same thought to make progress in logic. He himself hedged his own equipollence criterion with a number of provisos. In the literature on Frege, little attention has been paid to the problems these provisos raise. In this paper, I will argue that Fregeans have ignored these provisos at their peril. For without these provisos, Frege’s criterion yields wrong results; but with the provisos in place, it is of…Read more
  •  144
    According to Horwich’s use theory of meaning, the meaning of a word W is engendered by the underived acceptance of certain sentences containing W. Horwich applies this theory to provide an account of semantic stipulation: Semantic stipulation proceeds by deciding to accept sentences containing an as yet meaningless word W. Thereby one brings it about that W gets an underived acceptance property. Since a word’s meaning is constituted by its (basic) underived acceptance property, this decision end…Read more
  • Exempliflcation and IdealisationV
    In Gerhard Ernst, Jakob Steinbrenner & Oliver R. Scholz (eds.), From Logic to Art: Themes from Nelson Goodman, Ontos. pp. 7--207. 2009.
  •  3
    Bolzano sur le temps et la persistance
    Philosophiques 30 (1): 105-125. 2003.
    Comment une proposition qui affirme que a est fatigué le matin et n’est pas fatigué le midi peut-elle être vraie ? Bolzano soutient que toute proposition portant sur une chose contingente contient, dans la composante-sujet, la représentation d’un temps. Dans cet article, je reconstruis et évalue les arguments de Bolzano en les comparant à ceux de son adversaire principal, le tenant de la position selon laquelle toute proposition portant sur une chose contingente contient une copule renfermant la…Read more
  •  7
    ‘Portraying’ a Proposition 1
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1): 137-161. 2001.
    Hector‐Neri Castaüeda claimed in several papers that a proposition expressed by an indexical sentence (in a context of utterance) can be re‐expressed by means of an oratio obliqua clause (in a sentential context) that contains a quasi‐indicator. Robert M. Adams and Rogers Albritton have presented a counter‐argument that is accepted by Castaüeda himself. I will argue that the Adams/Albritton argument is not convincing: The argument uses several assumptions which could be disputed. The paper tries…Read more
  •  37
    Bolzano on conceptual and intuitive truth: the point and purpose of the distinction
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (1): 13-36. 2013.
    Bolzano incorporated Kant's distinction between intuitions and concepts into the doctrine of propositions by distinguishing between conceptual (Begriffssätze an sich) and intuitive propositions (Anschauungssätze an sich). An intuitive proposition contains at least one objective intuition, that is, a simple idea that represents exactly one object; a conceptual proposition contains no objective intuition. After Bolzano, philosophers dispensed with the distinction between conceptual and intuitive p…Read more
  •  3
    Knowledge, Possibility and Consciousness (review)
    Philosophy 77 (3): 454-471. 2002.
  • Ontologie Und Semantik (edited book)
    with M. Siebel
    Ontos Verlag. 2004.
  •  67
  •  56
    Unity without self: Brentano on the unity of consciousness
    In Denis Fisette & Guillaume Fréchette (eds.), Themes from Brentano, Editions Rodopi. pp. 44--67. 2013.
  •  40
    Frege on Conceptual and Propositional Analysis
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 81 (1): 235-257. 2010.
    In his Foundations of Arithmetic, Frege aims to extend our a priori arithmetical knowledge by answering the question what a natural number is. He rejects conceptual analysis as a method to acquire a priori knowledge . Later he unsuccessfully tried to solve the problems that beset conceptual analysis . If these problems remain unsolved, which rational method can he use to extend our a priori knowledge about numbers? I will argue that his fundamental arithmetical insight that numbers belong to con…Read more
  •  198
    States of affairs
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. forthcoming.
  •  127
    Devitt on the Epistemic Authority of Linguistic Intuitions
    Erkenntnis 71 (3): 395-405. 2009.
    Michael Devitt has argued that a satisfactory explanation of the authority of linguistic intuitions need not assume that they are derived from tacit knowledge of principles of grammar. Devitt’s Modest Explanation is based on a controversial construal of linguistic intuitions as meta-linguistic central-processor judgements. I will argue that there are non-judgemental responses to linguistic strings, linguistic seemings, which are evidence for linguistic theories. Devitt cannot account for their e…Read more
  • Brentano on the Doxastic Nature of Perceptual Experience
    History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 10. 2007.
    Brentano, the founder of phenomenology, argues in his manuscript “Von der Natur der Vorstellungen” that perception involves the belief in the object presented. The argument from revealed perceptual illusions argues that a perceptual experience can rationally persist even if one knows that it represents the world incorrectly, while the corresponding belief cannot rationally persist in this situation. For this reason, perceptual experiences cannot be beliefs or intrinsically connected to them. Bre…Read more
  •  5
    Objektive Apriorität
    Philosophia Scientiae 1 (3): 119-133. 1996.