•  47
    What Brentano criticizes in Reid
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (1). 2004.
    No abstract
  •  1
    Are Particulars or States of Affairs Given in
    In M. Reicher (ed.), States of Affairs, Ontos Verlag. pp. 30--129. 2009.
    The paper argues that the basic objects of perception are particulars, tropes in particular. It defends this view by proposing a response to the objection that we cannot perceive particulars without perceiving that it is so-and-so.
  •  95
    Is 'no' a force-indicator? No!
    Analysis 71 (3): 448-456. 2011.
  •  149
    According to Horwich’s use theory of meaning, the meaning of a word W is engendered by the underived acceptance of certain sentences containing W. Horwich applies this theory to provide an account of semantic stipulation: Semantic stipulation proceeds by deciding to accept sentences containing an as yet meaningless word W. Thereby one brings it about that W gets an underived acceptance property. Since a word’s meaning is constituted by its (basic) underived acceptance property, this decision end…Read more
  •  89
    According to Frege, we need a criterion for recognising when different sentences express the same thought to make progress in logic. He himself hedged his own equipollence criterion with a number of provisos. In the literature on Frege, little attention has been paid to the problems these provisos raise. In this paper, I will argue that Fregeans have ignored these provisos at their peril. For without these provisos, Frege’s criterion yields wrong results; but with the provisos in place, it is of…Read more
  • Exempliflcation and IdealisationV
    In Gerhard Ernst, Jakob Steinbrenner & Oliver R. Scholz (eds.), From Logic to Art: Themes from Nelson Goodman, Ontos. pp. 7--207. 2009.
  •  10
    ‘Portraying’ a Proposition 1
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1): 137-161. 2001.
    Hector‐Neri Castaüeda claimed in several papers that a proposition expressed by an indexical sentence (in a context of utterance) can be re‐expressed by means of an oratio obliqua clause (in a sentential context) that contains a quasi‐indicator. Robert M. Adams and Rogers Albritton have presented a counter‐argument that is accepted by Castaüeda himself. I will argue that the Adams/Albritton argument is not convincing: The argument uses several assumptions which could be disputed. The paper tries…Read more
  •  3
    Bolzano sur le temps et la persistance
    Philosophiques 30 (1): 105-125. 2003.
    Comment une proposition qui affirme que a est fatigué le matin et n’est pas fatigué le midi peut-elle être vraie ? Bolzano soutient que toute proposition portant sur une chose contingente contient, dans la composante-sujet, la représentation d’un temps. Dans cet article, je reconstruis et évalue les arguments de Bolzano en les comparant à ceux de son adversaire principal, le tenant de la position selon laquelle toute proposition portant sur une chose contingente contient une copule renfermant la…Read more
  •  37
    Bolzano on conceptual and intuitive truth: the point and purpose of the distinction
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (1): 13-36. 2013.
    Bolzano incorporated Kant's distinction between intuitions and concepts into the doctrine of propositions by distinguishing between conceptual (Begriffssätze an sich) and intuitive propositions (Anschauungssätze an sich). An intuitive proposition contains at least one objective intuition, that is, a simple idea that represents exactly one object; a conceptual proposition contains no objective intuition. After Bolzano, philosophers dispensed with the distinction between conceptual and intuitive p…Read more
  •  3
    Knowledge, Possibility and Consciousness (review)
    Philosophy 77 (3): 454-471. 2002.
  •  57
    Unity without self: Brentano on the unity of consciousness
    In Denis Fisette & Guillaume Fréchette (eds.), Themes from Brentano, Editions Rodopi. pp. 44--67. 2013.
  • Ontologie Und Semantik (edited book)
    with M. Siebel
    Ontos Verlag. 2004.
  •  67
  •  204
    States of affairs
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. forthcoming.
  •  41
    Frege on Conceptual and Propositional Analysis
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 81 (1): 235-257. 2010.
    In his Foundations of Arithmetic, Frege aims to extend our a priori arithmetical knowledge by answering the question what a natural number is. He rejects conceptual analysis as a method to acquire a priori knowledge . Later he unsuccessfully tried to solve the problems that beset conceptual analysis . If these problems remain unsolved, which rational method can he use to extend our a priori knowledge about numbers? I will argue that his fundamental arithmetical insight that numbers belong to con…Read more
  •  127
    Devitt on the Epistemic Authority of Linguistic Intuitions
    Erkenntnis 71 (3): 395-405. 2009.
    Michael Devitt has argued that a satisfactory explanation of the authority of linguistic intuitions need not assume that they are derived from tacit knowledge of principles of grammar. Devitt’s Modest Explanation is based on a controversial construal of linguistic intuitions as meta-linguistic central-processor judgements. I will argue that there are non-judgemental responses to linguistic strings, linguistic seemings, which are evidence for linguistic theories. Devitt cannot account for their e…Read more
  •  5
    Objektive Apriorität
    Philosophia Scientiae 1 (3): 119-133. 1996.
  • Brentano on the Doxastic Nature of Perceptual Experience
    History of Philosophy & Logical Analysis 10. 2007.
    Brentano, the founder of phenomenology, argues in his manuscript “Von der Natur der Vorstellungen” that perception involves the belief in the object presented. The argument from revealed perceptual illusions argues that a perceptual experience can rationally persist even if one knows that it represents the world incorrectly, while the corresponding belief cannot rationally persist in this situation. For this reason, perceptual experiences cannot be beliefs or intrinsically connected to them. Bre…Read more
  •  188
    A repair of Frege’s theory of thoughts
    Synthese 167 (1). 2009.
    Frege’s writings contain arguments for the thesis (i) that a thought expressed by a sentence S is a structured object whose composition pictures the composition of S, and for the thesis (ii) that a thought is an unstructured object. I will argue that Frege’s reasons for both (i) and (ii) are strong. Frege’s explanation of the difference in sense between logically equivalent sentences rests on assumption (i), while Frege’s claim that the same thought can be decomposed differently makes (ii) plaus…Read more
  •  74
    Self-representational theories of consciousness hold that a mental phenomenon is conscious if, and only if, it presents, among other things, itself. But in conscious perception one may lose oneself in the object perceived and not be aware of one’s perceiving. The paper develops a Brentano-inspired response to this objection. He follows Aristotle in holding that one is aware of one’s perceiving only ‘on the side’: when one perceives something one’s perception neither is nor can become observation…Read more
  •  96
    Truth via Sentential Quantification
    Dialogue 44 (3): 539-550. 2005.
    This paper is a critical evaluation of Kuenne's attempt to define truth via quantification into the position of a sentence
  •  8
    Perspectives on Perception (edited book)
    with Mary Margaret McCabe
    De Gruyter. 2007.
    Perception and its puzzles have given rise to philosophical reflection from antiquity to recent times: What do we perceive? How do we talk about what we perceive? What is the nature of our subjective experience? How can we talk about our subjective experience? In this book a distinguished group of philosophers addresses questions like these by drawing on historical and contemporary sources, illuminating the intersections between historical and contemporary philosophical discussion. They ask abou…Read more
  •  165
    Does the English demonstrative pronoun 'that' (including complex demonstratives of the form 'that F') have sense and reference? Unlike many other philosophers of language, Frege answers with a resounding 'No'. He held that the bearer of sense and reference is a so-called 'hybrid proper name' (Künne) that contains the demonstrative pronoun and specific circumstances of utterance such as glances and acts of pointing. In this paper I provide arguments for the thesis that demonstratives are hybrid p…Read more
  • Rigidity versus De Jure Rigidity
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 17 (1). 1998.
  •  763
    Proper Names and Practices: On Reference without Referents
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 81 (1): 105-118. 2010.
    This is review essay of Mark Sainsbury's Reference without Referents. Its main part is a critical discussion of Sainsbury's proposal for the individuation of proper name using practices.