•  18
    What is judgement? This question has exercised generations of philosophers. Early analytic philosophers such as Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein as well as phenomenologists such as Brentano, Husserl and Reinach changed how philosophers think about this question. The papers in this book explore and assess their contributions and help us to retrace their steps. In doing so we will get a clearer picture of judgement and the related notion of truth.
  •  65
    Does (affirmative) judgement have a logical dual, negative judgement? Whether there is such a logical dualism was hotly debated at the beginning of the twentieth century. Frege argued in ?Negation? (1918/9) that logic can dispense with negative judgement. Frege's arguments shaped the views of later generations of analytic philosophers, but they will not have convinced such opponents as Brentano or Windelband. These philosophers believed in negative judgement for psychological, not logical, reaso…Read more
  •  745
    Ever since Frege, propositions have played a central role in philosophy of language. Propositions are generally conceived as abstract objects that have truth conditions essentially and fulfill both the role of the meaning of sentences and of the objects or content of propositional attitudes. More recently, the abstract conception of propositions has given rise to serious dissatisfaction among a number of philosophers, who have instead proposed a conception of propositional content based on cogn…Read more
  •  109
    Frege’s Theory of Hybrid Proper Names Extended
    Mind 124 (495): 823-847. 2015.
    According to Frege, neither demonstratives nor indexicals are singular terms; only a demonstrative together with ‘circumstances accompanying its utterance’ has sense and singular reference. While this view seems defensible for demonstratives, where demonstrations serve as non-verbal signs, indexicals, especially pure indexicals like ‘I’, ‘here’, and ‘now’, seem not to be in need of completion by circumstances of utterance. In this paper I argue on the basis of independent reasons that indexicals…Read more
  •  158
    Frege's concept paradox and the mirroring principle
    Philosophical Quarterly 60 (238): 126-148. 2010.
    Frege held that singular terms can refer only to objects, not to concepts. I argue that the counter-intuitive consequences of this claim ('the concept paradox') arise from Frege's mirroring principle that an incomplete expression can only express an incomplete sense and stand for an incomplete reference. This is not, as is sometimes thought, merely because predicates and singular terms cannot be intersubstituted salva veritate ( congruitate ). The concept paradox, properly understood, poses ther…Read more
  •  94
    Samples as symbols
    Ratio 21 (3): 344-359. 2008.
    Nelson Goodman and, following him, Catherine Z. Elgin and Keith Lehrer have claimed that sometimes a sample is a symbol that stands for the property it is a sample of. The relation between the sample and the property it stands for is called 'exemplification' (Goodman, Elgin) or 'exemplarisation' (Lehrer). Goodman and Lehrer argue that the notion of exemplification sheds light on central problems in aesthetics and the philosophy of mind. However, while there seems to be a phenomenon to be capture…Read more
  •  106
    Proper Names: Philosophical and Linguistic Perspectives
    with Dolf Rami
    Erkenntnis 80 (2): 191-194. 2015.
    Proper names play an important role in our understanding of linguistic ‘aboutness’ or reference. For instance, the name-bearer relation is a good candidate for the paradigm of the reference relation: it provides us with our initial grip on this relation and controls our thinking about it. For this and other reasons proper names have been at the center of philosophical attention. However, proper names are as controversial as they are conceptually fundamental. Since Kripke’s seminal lectures Namin…Read more
  •  18
    Bolzano on the Source of Necessity: A Reply to Rusnock
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 21 (2). 2013.
    (2013). Bolzano on the Source of Necessity: A Reply to Rusnock. British Journal for the History of Philosophy: Vol. 21, No. 2, pp. 381-392. doi: 10.1080/09608788.2012.692661
  •  130
    Knowing the Facts
    Dialectica 65 (1): 75-86. 2011.
    Keith Hossack argues in his The Metaphysics of Knowledge(2007) that knowledge is a simple and metaphysically fundamental relation between a thinker and a fact: knowledge is uptake of fact. Facts are conceived as combinations of particulars and universals, distinct from true propositions. Hossacks's general argument is, roughly, that one can define central philosophical concepts (belief, content, justification, etc.) if one assumes that knowledge is primitive, but that knowledge cannot be defined…Read more
  • Vorfragen zur Wahrheit. Ein Traktat über kognitive Sprachen (review)
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 54 (2). 2000.
  • Intentional Phenomena in Context (edited book)
    with C. Stein
    Hamburg. 1996.
  •  56
    Intense heat immediately perceived is nothing distinct from a particular sort of pain
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 9 (1). 2001.
    The paper proposes a novel interpretation of Berkeley's so-called Assimilation Argument in the First Dialogue between Hylas and Philonous.
  •  1
    The Semantic Challenge to Russell's Principle
    Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy 6. 1998.
  •  11
    Bolzano and Analytic Philosophy (edited book)
    BRILL. 1997.
    Inhaltsverzeichnis/Table of Contents: Vorbemerkung/Preface. Dagfin FØLLESDAL: Bolzano's Legacy. Jan BERG: Bolzano, the Prescient Encyclopedist. Jan SEBESTIK: Bolzano, Exner and the Origins of Analytical Philosophy. Paul RUSNOCK: Bolzano and the Traditions of Analysis. Peter SIMONS: Bolzano on Collections. Ali BEHBOUD: Remarks on Bolzano's Collections. Mark SIEBEL: Variation, Derivability and Necessity. Edgar MORSCHER: Bolzano's Method of Variation: Three Puzzles. Rolf GEORGE: Bolzano's Programme…Read more
  •  80
    Does the truth-conditional theory of sense work for indexicals?
    Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (2): 119-137. 2010.
    Volume 6, Issue 2, 2001, Page 119-137.
  •  1
    Reviews: Reviews (review)
    Philosophy 85 (4): 563-567. 2010.
  •  13
    Bolzano's Sententialism
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 53 (1): 181-202. 1997.
    Bolzano holds that every sentence can be paraphrased into a sentence of the form "A has b". Bolzano's arguments for this claim are reconstructed and discussed. Since they crucially rely on Bolzano's notion of paraphrase, this notion is investigated in detail. Bolzano has usually been taken to require that in a correct paraphrase the sentence to be paraphrased and the paraphrasing sentence express the same proposition. In view of Bolzano's texts and systematical considerations this interpretation…Read more
  •  61
    ‘Portraying’ a Proposition
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (1): 137-161. 2001.
    Hector-Neri Castaneda claimed in several papers that a proposition expressed by an indexical sentence can be re-expressed by means of an oratio obliqua clause that contains a quasi-indicator. Robert M. Adams and Rogers Albritton have presented a counter-argument that is accepted by Castaneda himself. I will argue that the Adams/Albritton argument is not convincing: The argument uses several assumptions which could be disputed. The paper tries to develop a more direct argument against Castaneda’s…Read more
  •  31
    Bolzano et Husserl sur l'analyticité
    with Jocelyn Benoist
    Les Etudes Philosophiques 435-454. 2000.
    L'auteur expose la tentative faite par Bolzano de définir le concept de proposition en soi analytique à l'aide du concept de variation de représentation. Puis, il discute les difficultés qui résultent de ce modèle quant à la définition bolzanienne du concept étroit de vérité logiquement analytique ou de vérité logique. En conclusion, il compare la définition bolzanienne du concept de proposition en soi analytique et la définition husserlienne: celle-ci se découvre être une application de l'idée …Read more
  •  148
    Unsaturatedness: Wittgenstein's challenge, Frege's answer
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 109 (1pt1): 61-82. 2009.
    Frege holds the distinction between complete (saturated) and incomplete (unsaturated) things to be a basic distinction of logic. Many disagree. In this paper I will argue that one can defend Frege's distinction against criticism if one takes, inspired by Frege, a wh -question to be the paradigm incomplete expression.
  •  89
    Hope as a Primitive Mental State
    Ratio 28 (2): 207-222. 2015.
    We criticize attempts to define hope in terms of other psychological states and argue that hope is a primitive mental state whose nature can be illuminated by specifying key aspects of its functional profile
  • Review of M. Stepanians: Gottlob Frege zur Einführung (review)
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 57 (3). 2003.
  •  98
    Sense-only-signs: Frege on fictional proper names
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 82 (1): 375-400. 2011.
    I explore Frege's thesis that fictional proper names are supposed to have only sense and no reference. How can one make this thesis compatible with Frege's view that sense determines reference? By holding that fictional proper names are introduced in a particular kind of speech act. Or so I argue.
  •  39
    From Mental Holism to the Soul and Back
    The Monist 100 (1): 133-154. 2017.
    In his Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt Brentano proposed a view of consciousness that neither has room nor need for a subject of mental acts, a soul. Later he changed his mind: there is a soul that appears in consciousness. In this paper I will argue that Brentano’s change of view is not justified. The subjectless view of consciousness can be defended against Brentano’s argument and it is superior to its predecessor.