Princeton University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1995
Cambridge, Cambridgeshire, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
  •  122
    Intention detecting
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (172): 298-318. 1994.
    Crispin Wright has argued that our concept of intention is extension-determining, and that this explains why we are so good at knowing our intentions: it does so by subverting the idea that we detect them. This paper has two aims. The first is to make sense of Wright's claim that intention is extension-determining; this is achieved by comparing his position to that of analytic functionalism. The second is to show that it doesn't follow from this that we do not detect our intentions. Wright has c…Read more
  •  121
    Positivism and the internal point of view
    Law and Philosophy 17 (s 5-6): 597-625. 1998.
    Can one consistently (i) be a positivist, and (ii) think that the internal attitude to the law is a moral attitude? Two objections are raised in the literature. The first is that the combination is straight-out contradictory. The second is that if the internal attitude is a moral attitude, those who take it cannot be positivists. Arguments from Shiner, Goldsworthy and Raz are examined. It is concluded that neither objection works. The arguments are based on scope errors, conflations of what is s…Read more
  •  118
    From Determinism to Resignation, and How to Stop It
    In Andy Clark, Julian Kiverstein & Tillman Vierkant (eds.), Decomposing the Will, Oxford University Press. 2013.
    A few philosophers have held that determinism should lead to an attitude of resignation: since what will be will be, there is no point trying to influence the future. That argument has rightly been seen as mistaken. But a plausible parallel argument leads from the thesis of predictability---the thesis that it can be known what will happen---to an attitude of resignation. So if predictability is true, our normal practical attitudes may well be deeply mistaken. Fortunately, whilst determinism is a…Read more
  •  113
    Empathy and animal ethics
    In Dale Jamieson (ed.), Singer and His Critics, Oxford University Press. 1998.
    In responding to the challenge that we cannot know that animals feel pain, Peter Singer says: We can never directly experience the pain of another being, whether that being is human or not. When I see my daughter fall and scrape her knee, I know that she feels pain because of the way she behaves—she cries, she tells me her knee hurts, she rubs the sore spot, and so on. I know that I myself behave in a somewhat similar—if more inhibited—way when I feel pain, and so I accept that my daughter feels…Read more
  •  110
    Minimalism about truth
    In B. Garrett & K. Mulligan (eds.), Themes from Wittgenstein, Anu Working Papers in Philosophy 4. 1993.
    My main task here is first to distinguish, and then to map out possibilities. I won’t be concerned to argue for a certain position as much as to argue that various combinations of positions are consistent. In particular, I want to argue that a commitment to minimalism about truth does not bring an automatic commitment to what has been called a minimalist theory of truth-aptitude: the claim that every assertoric sentence which is used in a systematic way will be either true or false. Nor does min…Read more
  •  95
    Reason, value and the muggletonians
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (3). 1996.
    Michael Smith has argued that to value an action is to believe that if one were fully rational one would desire that one perform it. I offer the Muggletonians as a counter-example. The Muggletonians, a 17th century English sect, believed that reason was the path of the Devil. They believed that their fully rational selves - rational in just Smith's sense - would have blasphemed against God; and that their rational selves would have wanted their actual selves to do likewise. But blaspheming again…Read more
  •  95
    Lying About
    Journal of Philosophy 116 (2): 99-105. 2019.
    We do not report lies with that-clauses but with about-clauses: he lied about x. It is argued that this is because the content of a lie need not be the content of what is said, and about-clauses give us the requisite flexibility. Building on the work of Stephen Yablo, an attempt is made to give an account of lying about in terms of partial content and topic.
  •  87
    Comments on Ralph Wedgwood’s The Nature of Normativity
    Philosophical Studies 151 (3): 449-457. 2010.
    Ralph Wedgwood has written a big book: not in terms of pages (though there are plenty) but in terms of scope and ambition. Scope, in that he addresses many of the central issues around normativity, providing an account of the semantics of ‘ought’, and then a metaphysics and an epistemology to go with it; ambition in that so much of this is novel. Along the way there are myriad discussion of relevant philosophical background issues and of methodology.
  •  82
    Review: The Illusion of Conscious Will (review)
    Mind 113 (449): 218-221. 2004.
  •  81
    Intentions, response-dependence, and immunity from error
    In P. Menzies (ed.), Response Dependent Concepts, Anu Working Papers in Philosophy 1. 1991.
    You are, I suspect, exceedingly good at knowing what you intend to do. In saying this I pay you no special compliment. Knowing what one intends is the normal state to be in. And this cries out for some explanation. How is it that we are so authoritative about our own intentions? There are two different approaches that one can take in answering this question. The first credits us with special perceptual powers which we use when we examine our own minds. On this view we detect our own mental state…Read more
  •  72
    Modeling Legal Rules
    In Andrei Marmor & Scott Soames (eds.), Philosophical Foundations of Language in the Law, Oxford University Press. 2011.
    Building on earlier work, this paper develops a model of legal rules that admit of exceptions but are nonetheless governed by classical logic. The account is defended against alternative accounts that construe legal rules as generics, or as default rules.
  •  68
    In a characteristic passage John McDowell says: [T]his is one of those set-ups that are familiar in philosophy, in which a supposedly exhaustive choice confers a spurious plausibility on a philosophical position. The apparent plausibility is not intrinsic to the position, but reflects an assumed framework; when one looks at the position on its own, the plausibility crumbles away ... In such a situation, the thing to do is to query the assumption that seems to force the choice.
  •  61
    Addiction, Self‐Signalling and the Deep Self
    Mind and Language 31 (3): 300-313. 2016.
    Addicts may simply deny that they are addicted; or they may use self-signalling to try to provide evidence that giving up is not worthwhile. I provide an account that shows how easy it is to provide apparent evidence either that the addiction is so bad that it cannot be escaped; or that there is no real addiction, and hence nothing to escape. I suggest that the most effective way of avoiding this is to avoid self-signalling altogether.
  •  59
    Too much medicine: not enough trust?
    with Zoë Fritz
    Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (1): 31-35. 2019.
    As many studies around the theme of ‘too much medicine’ attest, investigations are being ordered with increasing frequency; similarly the threshold for providing treatment has lowered. Our contention is that trust is a significant factor in influencing this, and that understanding the relationship between trust and investigations and treatments will help clinicians and policymakers ensure ethical decisions are more consistently made. Drawing on the philosophical literature, we investigate the na…Read more
  •  57
    Animals and Alternatives
    The Philosophers' Magazine 81 14-15. 2018.
  •  55
    Crime as Prime
    The Law and Ethics of Human Rights 9 (2): 181-193. 2015.
    Traditional interpretations of legal doctrine have seen the actus reus and the mens rea as independent elements of a crime. Here it is argued that various puzzles surrounding the nature of intent and of attempt can be better addressed if we reject that idea. Following Williamson’s account of knowledge, it is suggested that the two are inseparable. The crime consists in the performance of an intentional act. It follows that an act has been performed and that the performer is in a certain mental s…Read more
  •  54
    In (Holton 1996) I argued that the account of value that Michael Smith has offered was vulnerable to a counter-example in the person of the Muggletonians. Smith argued, roughly, that what one values is what one would desire if one were fully rational. I objected that the Muggletonians held the path of Reason to be the path to evil. According to them, a fully rational person would have their desires so corrupted that they would become, quite literally, Satan. Thus they believed that their fully r…Read more
  •  51
    Review of Feeling Like It, by Tamar Schapiro (review)
    Mind. forthcoming.
  •  45
    The Good/Bad Asymmetry
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 35 (1): 26-32. 2018.
  •  43
    Memory, Persons and Dementia
    Studies in Christian Ethics 29 (3): 256-260. 2016.
    Memory is a complex phenomenon, so the loss of memory that occurs in dementia is equally complex. Accounts that deny personhood to dementia sufferers typically fail to accommodate that complexity.
  •  38
    The Illusion of Conscious Will
    Mind 113 (449): 218-221. 2004.
  •  36
    Some telling examples: A reply to Tsohatzidis
    Journal of Pragmatics 28 625-628. 1997.
    In a recent paper Savas Tsohatzidis has provided a number of putative counterexamples to the well-attested Kartunnen-Vendler (K-V) thesis that the use of 'tell' with a wh-complement requires that the speaker spoke truthfully. His counterexamples are sentences like: (1) Old John told us who he saw in the fog, but it turned out that he was mistaken. I argue that such examples do not serve to refute the K-V thesis. Rather, they are examples of a more general phenomenon that I label participant proj…Read more
  •  34
    Not Thinking About the Worst
    The Philosophers' Magazine 90 50-53. 2020.
  •  33
    Too much medicine and the poor climate of trust
    with Zoe Fritz
    Journal of Medical Ethics 45 (11): 748-749. 2019.
    Joshua Parker has made many interesting points, and we welcome the opportunity to develop the ideas of ‘Too Much Medicine, Not Enough Trust’. We will address: (i) the asymmetry between the trust that patients extend to doctors, and the trust that doctors extend to patients; (ii) our reasons for doubting that litigation or complaints reflect a betrayal of the patient–doctor relationship and (iii) the importance of institutional trust, both for the doctor and the patient.
  •  31
    The case for open access
    The Philosophers' Magazine 65 10-13. 2014.
  •  9
    Primitive Self‐Ascription
    In Barry Loewer & Jonathan Schaffer (eds.), A Companion to David Lewis, Wiley. 2015.
    David Lewis's account of the de se has two parts. The first part involves treating the objects of the attitudes, not as propositions but as properties. The second part involves treating our attitude to these properties as that of self‐ascription. In particular, much recent literature has tried to incorporate his account simply by treating the objects of the attitudes as centered worlds, where a centered world is an ordered pair of a possible world together with a spatiotemporal location. The exp…Read more