•  441
    Williamson on the A Priori and the Analytic (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 82 (2): 488-497. 2010.
    This essay criticizes Williamson’s attempt, in his book, The Philosophy of Philosophy, to undermine the interest of the a priori–a posteriori distinction. Williamson’s argument turns on several large claims. The first is that experience often plays a role intermediate between evidential and merely enabling, and that this poses a difficulty for giving a theoretically satisfying account of the distinction. The second is that there are no constitutive understanding–assent links. Both of these claim…Read more
  •  129
    O labirinto do relativismo moral
    Revista Inquietude 2 (2): 238-245. 2011.
    Portuguese translation of "The Maze of Moral Relativism" by Janos Biro.
  •  327
    The Transparency of Mental Content
    Philosophical Perspectives 8 33-50. 1994.
    I believe that the notion of epistemic transparency does play an important role in our ordinary conception of mental content and I want to say what that role is. Unfortunately, the task is a large one; here I am able only to begin on its outline. I shall proceed somewhat indirectly, beginning with a discussion of externalist conceptions of mental content. I shall show that such conceptions violate epistemic transparency to an extent that has not been fully appreciated. Subsequently, I shall look…Read more
  •  209
    This essay attempts to clarify the project of explaining the possibility of ‘blind reasoning’—namely, of basic logical inferences to which we are entitled without our having an explicit justification for them. The role played by inferentialism in this project is examined and objections made to inferentialism by Paolo Casalegno and Timothy Williamson are answered. Casalegno proposes a recipe for formulating a counterexample to any proposed constitutive inferential role by imaging a subject who un…Read more
  •  727
    The normativity of content
    Philosophical Issues 13 (1): 31-45. 2003.
    It is very common these days to come across the claim that the notions of mental content and linguistic meaning are normative notions. In the work of many philosophers, it plays a pivotal role. Saul Kripke made it the centerpiece of his influential discussion of Wittgenstein’s treatment of rulefollowing and private language; he used it to argue that the notions of meaning and content cannot be understood in naturalistic terms. Kripke’s formulations tend to be in terms of the notion of linguistic…Read more
  •  225
    Explaining musical experience
    In Kathleen Stock (ed.), Philosophers on Music: Experience, Meaning, and Work, Oxford University Press. pp. 117. 2007.
    I start with the observation that we often respond to a musical performance with emotion -- even if it is just the performance of a piece of absolute music, unaccompanied by text, title or programme. We can be exhilarated after a Rossini overture brought off with subtlety and panache; somber and melancholy after Furtlanger’s performance of the slow movement of the Eroica. And so forth. These emotions feel like the real thing to me – or anyway very close to the real thing. When one experiences th…Read more
  •  85
    Reply to Otero's “Boghossian's Inference Argument against Content Externalism Reversed”
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 89 (1): 182-184. 2014.
    In my (1992, 1994), I argued that introspective accessibility of facts about sameness and difference ofthe concepts exercised in our thoughts plays a pivotal role in our most basic conceptions of rational agency and rational explanation. In particular, I argued that any theory of concepts that allows for such failures of (epistemic) transparency faces a serious difficulty: it seems committed to mis-describing the conditions underwhich agents are rational. ...
  •  86
    Blind rule-following
    In Annalisa Coliva (ed.), Mind, meaning, and knowledge: themes from the philosophy of Crispin Wright, Oxford University Press. pp. 27-48. 2012.
    In this chapter a new problem about rule-following is outlined, one that is distinct both from Kripke’s and Wright’s versions of the problem. This new problem cannot be correctly responsed to, as Kripke’s can, by invoking Wright’s Intentional Account of rule-following. The upshot might be called, following Kant, an antinomy of pure reason: we both must — and cannot — make sense of someone’s following a rule. The chapter explores various ways out of this antinomy without here endorsing any of the…Read more
  •  203
    Reasoning and Reflection: A Reply to Kornblith
    Analysis 76 (1): 41-54. 2016.
    Hilary Kornblith’s book is motivated by the conviction that philosophers have tended to overvalue and overemphasize reflection in their accounts of central philosophical phenomena. He seeks to pinpoint this tendency and to correct it. Kornblith’s claim is not without precedent. It is an oft-repeated theme of 20th-century philosophy that philosophers have tended to give ‘overly intellectualized’ accounts of important phenomena. One thinks here of Wittgenstein, Ryle and many others. One version of…Read more
  •  1407
    What is inference?
    Philosophical Studies 169 (1): 1-18. 2014.
    In some previous work, I tried to give a concept-based account of the nature of our entitlement to certain very basic inferences (see the papers in Part III of Boghossian 2008b). In this previous work, I took it for granted, along with many other philosophers, that we understood well enough what it is for a person to infer. In this paper, I turn to thinking about the nature of inference itself. This topic is of great interest in its own right and surprisingly understudied by philosophers. A corr…Read more
  •  45
    Naturalizing content
    In Barry M. Loewer (ed.), Meaning in Mind: Fodor and His Critics, Blackwell. 1991.
    The conviction that intentional realism requires intentional reductionism has the philosophy of mind in its grip. Thus, Jerry Fodor: .... It is worth noting — if only because it so seldom is nowadays — that this rationale for the naturalistic conviction begs a question that doesn't obviously deserve to be begged. Why, indeed, must we think that no property can be real unless it is identical with, or supervenient upon, the properties that appear in the catalogues provided by physics? There is, I …Read more
  •  12
    The Sokal Hoax
    In Robert Klee (ed.), Scientific Inquiry: Readings in the Philosophy of Science, Oxford University Press. pp. 265-274. 1999.
    Reprint of "What the Sokal Hoax Ought to Teach Us", Times Literary Supplement (1996)
  •  946
    How Are Objective Epistemic Reasons Possible?
    Philosophical Studies 106 (1-2): 1-40. 2001.
    Epistemic relativism has the contemporary academy in its grip. Not merely in the United States, but seemingly everywhere, most scholars working in the humanities and the social sciences seem to subscribe to some form of it. Even where the label is repudiated, the view is embraced. Sometimes the relativism in question concerns truth, sometimes justification. The core impulse appears to be a relativism about knowledge. The suspicion is widespread that what counts as knowledge in one cultural, or b…Read more
  •  503
    Seeking The Real
    Philosophical Studies 108 (1-2): 223-238. 2002.
    A critical discussion of Barry Stroud's claim, in his book The Quest for Reality, that we could never rationally arrive at the conclusion that, for example, the world is not really colored.
  •  80
    Quine is usually read as arguing either for a non-factualism about analyticity (1) ... Or, at the very least, for an error thesis about it: (2) ... These attributions — including the stronger non-factualist thesis — seem licensed by many passages, including the famous one which concludes Quine's discussion in "Two Dogmas" ... Nevertheless, Paul Horwich does not wish to read Quine as endorsing either (1) or (2). He certainly does not wish to attribute (1) to him. And he wishes to attribute only a…Read more
  •  2230
    Three Kinds of Relativism
    In Steven D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Blackwell. 2011.
    The paper looks at three big ideas that have been associated with the term “relativism.” The first maintains that some property has a higher-degree than might have been thought. The second that the judgments in a particular domain of discourse are capable only of relative truth and not of absolute truth And the third, which I dub with the oxymoronic label “absolutist relativism,” seeks to locate relativism in our acceptance of certain sorts of spare absolutist principles. -/- The first idea is w…Read more
  •  43
    Review: Sense, Reference and Rule-Following (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1). 1994.
    Review of The Metaphysics of Meaning by Jerrold Katz
  •  534
    What the externalist can know A Priori
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 97 (2): 161-75. 1997.
    Compatibilism combines an externalist view of mental content with a doctrine of privileged self‐knowledge. The essay presents a reductio of compatibilism by arguing that if compatibilism were true, we would be in a position to know certain facts about the world a priori, facts that no one can reasonably believe are knowable a priori. Whether this should be taken to cast doubt on externalism or privileged self‐knowledge is not discussed. Consideration is given to the ’empty case’—the case in whic…Read more
  •  235
    Précis of Fear of Knowledge
    Philosophical Studies 141 (3): 377-378. 2008.
    Fear of Knowledge was in many ways an exercise in foolhardiness. It was to be a short book, accessible to the general reader, that would treat some of the trickiest issues in the foundations theory of knowledge, but that would nevertheless not seriously shortchange the subtleties that they involve. Someone should have warned me
  •  457
    The transparency of mental content revisited (review)
    Philosophical Studies 155 (3): 457-465. 2011.
  •  632
    Is Meaning Normative?
    In Nimtz Christian & Beckermann Ansgar (eds.), Philosophy – Science – Scientific Philosophy. Main Lectures and Colloquia of GAP.5, Fifth International Congress of the Society for Analytical Philosophy, Bielefeld, 22–26 September 2003, Paperborn. pp. 205-218. 2005.
    The claim that meaning is a normative notion has become very influential in recent philosophy: in the work of many philosophers it plays a pivotal role. Although one can trace the idea of the normativity of meaning at least as far back as Kant, much of the credit for its recent influence must go to Saul Kripke who made the thesis a centerpiece of his much-admired treatment of Wittgenstein’s discussion of rule-following and private language....
  •  147
    The Perception of Music: Comments on Peacocke
    British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (1): 71-76. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  115
    Experience, Phenomenal Character and Epistemic Justification
    Philosophical Issues 25 (1): 243-251. 2015.
    Suppose that, while looking at a red strawberry under normal conditions, I form the judgment that there is something red in front of me. We may stipulate that my judgment is based on my experience of the red strawberry. As a result, my judgment is justified by my experience. In virtue of what aspects of my experience is my judgment justified? In particular: Does the phenomenal character of my experience of something red play an important role in the justification of my judgment? I want to examin…Read more
  •  76
    Reply to Schiffer
    Philosophical Issues 2 39-42. 1992.
    Reply to Schiffer's comment on Externalism and Inference.
  •  1117
    Color as a secondary quality
    Mind 98 (January): 81-103. 1989.
    Should a principle of charity be applied to the interpretation of the colour concepts exercised in visual experience? We think not. We shall argue, for one thing, that the grounds for applying a principle of charity are lacking in the case of colour concepts. More importantly, we shall argue that attempts at giving the experience of colour a charitable interpretation either fail to respect obvious features of that experience or fail to interpret it charitably, after all. Charity to visual experi…Read more
  •  195
    Rules, Meaning and Intention – Discussion (review)
    Philosophical Studies 124 (2): 185-197. 2005.
    Review of Philip Pettit’s Rules, Reasons and Norms.
  •  601
    What is Relativism?
    In Patrick Greenough & Michael P. Lynch (eds.), Truth and Relativism, Clarendon Press. pp. 13--37. 2006.
    Many philosophers, however, have been tempted to be relativists about specific domains of discourse, especially about those domains that have a normative character. Gilbert Harman, for example, has defended a relativistic view of morality, Richard Rorty a relativistic view of epistemic justification, and Crispin Wright a relativistic view of judgments of taste.¹ But what exactly is it to be a relativist about a given domain of discourse? The term ‘‘relativism’’ has, of course, been used in a bewil…Read more
  •  128
    Our Grasp of the Concept of Truth: Reflections on Künne
    Dialectica 64 (4): 553-563. 2010.
    Wolfgang Künne's Conceptions of Truth (2003) is a magnificent achievement. Wonderfully clear, erudite, compendious, honest and insightful on some very tricky issues – these are some of its many virtues. I have benefited a great deal from studying it. In this short note, I will concentrate on Künne's own positive proposal about the concept of truth, his modestly named ‘Modest Account’. I will raise some questions about its ultimate viability.
  •  388
    The status of content
    Philosophical Review 99 (2): 157-84. 1990.
    An irrealist conception of a given region of discourse is the view that no real properties answer to the central predicates of the region in question. Any such conception emerges, invariably, as the result of the interaction of two forces. An account of the meaning of the central predicates, along with a conception of the sorts of property the world may contain, conspire to show that, if the predicates of the region are taken to express properties, their extensions would have to be deemed unifor…Read more
  •  266
    Inference and insight (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3). 2001.
    All of us are disposed to reason according to the rule of inference modus ponens : from.