•  941
    How Are Objective Epistemic Reasons Possible?
    Philosophical Studies 106 (1-2): 1-40. 2001.
    Epistemic relativism has the contemporary academy in its grip. Not merely in the United States, but seemingly everywhere, most scholars working in the humanities and the social sciences seem to subscribe to some form of it. Even where the label is repudiated, the view is embraced. Sometimes the relativism in question concerns truth, sometimes justification. The core impulse appears to be a relativism about knowledge. The suspicion is widespread that what counts as knowledge in one cultural, or b…Read more
  •  12
    The Sokal Hoax
    In Robert Klee (ed.), Scientific Inquiry: Readings in the Philosophy of Science, Oxford University Press. pp. 265-274. 1999.
    Reprint of "What the Sokal Hoax Ought to Teach Us", Times Literary Supplement (1996)
  •  502
    Seeking The Real
    Philosophical Studies 108 (1-2): 223-238. 2002.
    A critical discussion of Barry Stroud's claim, in his book The Quest for Reality, that we could never rationally arrive at the conclusion that, for example, the world is not really colored.
  •  78
    Quine is usually read as arguing either for a non-factualism about analyticity (1) ... Or, at the very least, for an error thesis about it: (2) ... These attributions — including the stronger non-factualist thesis — seem licensed by many passages, including the famous one which concludes Quine's discussion in "Two Dogmas" ... Nevertheless, Paul Horwich does not wish to read Quine as endorsing either (1) or (2). He certainly does not wish to attribute (1) to him. And he wishes to attribute only a…Read more
  •  43
    Review: Sense, Reference and Rule-Following (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54 (1). 1994.
    Review of The Metaphysics of Meaning by Jerrold Katz
  •  2218
    Three Kinds of Relativism
    In Steven D. Hales (ed.), A Companion to Relativism, Blackwell. 2011.
    The paper looks at three big ideas that have been associated with the term “relativism.” The first maintains that some property has a higher-degree than might have been thought. The second that the judgments in a particular domain of discourse are capable only of relative truth and not of absolute truth And the third, which I dub with the oxymoronic label “absolutist relativism,” seeks to locate relativism in our acceptance of certain sorts of spare absolutist principles. -/- The first idea is w…Read more
  •  231
    Précis of Fear of Knowledge
    Philosophical Studies 141 (3): 377-378. 2008.
    Fear of Knowledge was in many ways an exercise in foolhardiness. It was to be a short book, accessible to the general reader, that would treat some of the trickiest issues in the foundations theory of knowledge, but that would nevertheless not seriously shortchange the subtleties that they involve. Someone should have warned me
  •  532
    What the externalist can know A Priori
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 97 (2): 161-75. 1997.
    Compatibilism combines an externalist view of mental content with a doctrine of privileged self‐knowledge. The essay presents a reductio of compatibilism by arguing that if compatibilism were true, we would be in a position to know certain facts about the world a priori, facts that no one can reasonably believe are knowable a priori. Whether this should be taken to cast doubt on externalism or privileged self‐knowledge is not discussed. Consideration is given to the ’empty case’—the case in whic…Read more
  •  629
    Is Meaning Normative?
    In Nimtz Christian & Beckermann Ansgar (eds.), Philosophy – Science – Scientific Philosophy. Main Lectures and Colloquia of GAP.5, Fifth International Congress of the Society for Analytical Philosophy, Bielefeld, 22–26 September 2003, Paperborn. pp. 205-218. 2005.
    The claim that meaning is a normative notion has become very influential in recent philosophy: in the work of many philosophers it plays a pivotal role. Although one can trace the idea of the normativity of meaning at least as far back as Kant, much of the credit for its recent influence must go to Saul Kripke who made the thesis a centerpiece of his much-admired treatment of Wittgenstein’s discussion of rule-following and private language....
  •  450
    The transparency of mental content revisited (review)
    Philosophical Studies 155 (3): 457-465. 2011.
  •  115
    Experience, Phenomenal Character and Epistemic Justification
    Philosophical Issues 25 (1): 243-251. 2015.
    Suppose that, while looking at a red strawberry under normal conditions, I form the judgment that there is something red in front of me. We may stipulate that my judgment is based on my experience of the red strawberry. As a result, my judgment is justified by my experience. In virtue of what aspects of my experience is my judgment justified? In particular: Does the phenomenal character of my experience of something red play an important role in the justification of my judgment? I want to examin…Read more
  •  145
    The Perception of Music: Comments on Peacocke
    British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (1): 71-76. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  71
    Reply to Schiffer
    Philosophical Issues 2 39-42. 1992.
    Reply to Schiffer's comment on Externalism and Inference.
  •  1100
    Color as a secondary quality
    Mind 98 (January): 81-103. 1989.
    Should a principle of charity be applied to the interpretation of the colour concepts exercised in visual experience? We think not. We shall argue, for one thing, that the grounds for applying a principle of charity are lacking in the case of colour concepts. More importantly, we shall argue that attempts at giving the experience of colour a charitable interpretation either fail to respect obvious features of that experience or fail to interpret it charitably, after all. Charity to visual experi…Read more
  •  192
    Rules, Meaning and Intention – Discussion (review)
    Philosophical Studies 124 (2): 185-197. 2005.
    Review of Philip Pettit’s Rules, Reasons and Norms.
  •  125
    Our Grasp of the Concept of Truth: Reflections on Künne
    Dialectica 64 (4): 553-563. 2010.
    Wolfgang Künne's Conceptions of Truth (2003) is a magnificent achievement. Wonderfully clear, erudite, compendious, honest and insightful on some very tricky issues – these are some of its many virtues. I have benefited a great deal from studying it. In this short note, I will concentrate on Künne's own positive proposal about the concept of truth, his modestly named ‘Modest Account’. I will raise some questions about its ultimate viability.
  •  600
    What is Relativism?
    In Patrick Greenough & Michael P. Lynch (eds.), Truth and Relativism, Clarendon Press. pp. 13--37. 2006.
    Many philosophers, however, have been tempted to be relativists about specific domains of discourse, especially about those domains that have a normative character. Gilbert Harman, for example, has defended a relativistic view of morality, Richard Rorty a relativistic view of epistemic justification, and Crispin Wright a relativistic view of judgments of taste.¹ But what exactly is it to be a relativist about a given domain of discourse? The term ‘‘relativism’’ has, of course, been used in a bewil…Read more
  •  263
    Inference and insight (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3). 2001.
    All of us are disposed to reason according to the rule of inference modus ponens : from.
  •  388
    The status of content
    Philosophical Review 99 (2): 157-84. 1990.
    An irrealist conception of a given region of discourse is the view that no real properties answer to the central predicates of the region in question. Any such conception emerges, invariably, as the result of the interaction of two forces. An account of the meaning of the central predicates, along with a conception of the sorts of property the world may contain, conspire to show that, if the predicates of the region are taken to express properties, their extensions would have to be deemed unifor…Read more
  •  146
    The gospel of relaxation
    The New Republic. 2001.
    Pragmatism is America’s distinctive contribution to the history of philosophical thought, though there has always been some dispute about exactly what doctrine it is supposed to name. The philosopher and psychologist William James, in a lecture given at Berkeley in 1898, attributed the view to..
  •  428
    Epistemic analyticity: A defense
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 66 (1): 15-35. 2003.
    The paper is a defense of the project of explaining the a priori via the notion of meaning or concept possession. It responds to certain objections that have been made to this project—in particular, that there can be no epistemically analytic sentences that are not also metaphysically analytic, and that the notion of implicit definition cannot explain a priori entitlement. The paper goes on to distinguish between two different ways in which facts about meaning might generate facts about entitlem…Read more
  •  63
    Reply to Amini and Caldwell, “Boghossian’s Refutation of Relativism”
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 2 (1): 45-49. 2012.
    Majid Amini and Christopher Caldwell charge that I misconstrue the relation between relativism and constructivism, on the one hand, and between relativism and skepticism, on the other. In this brief response, I rebut their charges.
  •  322
    The Maze of Moral Relativism
    New York Times. 2011.
    Relativism about morality has come to play an increasingly important role in contemporary culture. To many thoughtful people, and especially to those who are unwilling to derive their morality from a religion, it appears unavoidable. Where would absolute facts about right and wrong come from, they reason, if there is no supreme being to decree them? We should reject moral absolutes, even as we keep our moral convictions, allowing that there can be right and wrong relative to this or that moral…Read more
  •  1066
    Physicalist theories of color
    Philosophical Review 100 (January): 67-106. 1991.
    The dispute between realists about color and anti-realists is actually a dispute about the nature of color properties. The disputants do not disagree over what material objects are like. Rather, they disagree over whether any of the uncontroversial facts about material objects--their powers to cause visual experiences, their dispositions to reflect incident light, their atomic makeup, and so on--amount to their having colors. The disagreement is thus about which properties colors are and, in par…Read more
  •  283
    What the Externalist Can Know A Priori
    Philosophical Issues 9 197-211. 1998.
    Compatibilism combines an externalist view of mental content with a doctrine of privileged self‐knowledge. The essay presents a reductio of compatibilism by arguing that if compatibilism were true, we would be in a position to know certain facts about the world a priori, facts that no one can reasonably believe are knowable a priori. Whether this should be taken to cast doubt on externalism or privileged self‐knowledge is not discussed. Consideration is given to the ’empty case’—the case in whic…Read more
  •  259
    Inferential role semantics and the analytic/synthetic distinction
    Philosophical Studies 73 (2-3): 109-122. 1994.
    This is a critical discussion of Jerry Fodor and Ernie Lepore's "Holism". The paper questions the existence of a slippery slope from some inferential liaisons are constitutive of meaning' to all inferential liaisons are constitutive of meaning'. "Interalia", it defends the existence of an analytic/synthetic distinction
  •  463
    I agree with Sosa that intuitions are best thought of as attractions to believe a certain proposition merely on the basis of understanding it. However, I don't think it is constitutive of them that they supply strictly foundational justification for the propositions they justify, though I do believe that it is important that the intuition of a suitable subject be thought of as a prima facie justification for his intuitive judgment, independently of the reliability of his underlying capacities. I…Read more