• The God of Spinoza: A Philosophical Study. By Richard Mason (review)
    The European Legacy 7 (1): 115-115. 2002.
  •  12
    Encyclopedia of empiricism (edited book)
    with Edward Barbanell
    Greenwood Press. 1997.
    Featuring more than 150 articles by more than 70 leading scholars, this is the first encyclopedia devoted to empiricism. The _Encyclopedia of Empiricism_ serves four main purposes. First, it provides a convenient source for scholars and students seeking information on particular figures, topics, or doctrines, specifically in their relation to empiricism as an historical movement or to empiricism as a broader tendency of thought. Because each entry contains a brief bibliography of primary and sec…Read more
  •  2
    Teleology in Spinoza and Early Modern Rationalism
    In Rocco J. Gennaro & Charles Huenemann (eds.), New essays on the rationalists, Oxford University Press. 1999.
    This chapter seeks to establish that Spinoza accepts the legitimacy of many teleological explanations; that in two important respects, Leibniz's view of teleology is not more, and perhaps even less, Aristotleian than Descartes's; and that among Descartes, Spinoza, and Leibniz, it is Spinoza who holds the view of teleology closest to that of Aristotle. The arguments for derive from examinations of Spinoza's doctrine of conatus, critical analysis of Jonathan Bennett's proposed grounds for interpre…Read more
  • A Small Tincture of Pyrrhonism
    In Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian skepticism, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    This essay distinguishes varieties of skepticism along six dimensions. It argues that Hume is unmitigated in his rational support skepticism and in his prescriptive skepticism about certain “high and distant enquiries”, but mitigated in his general practising skepticism and in his general epistemic merit skepticism. Hume’s skepticism must be seen as mitigated in these ways in order to solve four central puzzles for Hume scholars.
  • Spinoza's Conatus Argument
    In Olli Koistinen & John Ivan Biro (eds.), Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes, Oup Usa. 2002.
    This essay contends that Spinoza’s argument for the conatus doctrine does not commit any of the five fallacies of equivocation. The key to a better understanding of his argument lies in a Spinoza’s “theory of inherence” — that is, his theory of what it is to be “in” something. Spinoza’s conatus argument is a valid demonstration from Spinozistic premises about inherence, conception, causation, and related matters. These premises reflect his deep commitment to a rigorous Principle of Sufficient Re…Read more
  • David Hume’s “Title Principle,” as it has come to be called, is a specification of the normative scope of reason: “Where reason is lively, and mixes itself with some propensity, it ought to be assented to. Where it does not, it never can have any title to operate on us.” This chapter seeks to answer four central questions about the principle. First, what does Hume mean by “reason” in it? Second, what particular kinds of beliefs does it mandate or disallow? Third, what kind of normativity is expr…Read more
  •  34
    The literary arts in Hume's science of the fancy
    Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 44 (108): 161-179. 2003.
    Philosophers have long disagreed about whether poetry, drama, and other literary arts are important to philosophy and among those who believe that they are important, explanations of that importance have differed greatly. This paper aims to explain and illustrate some of the reasons why Hume found literature to be an important topic for philosophy and philosophers. Philosophy, he holds, can help to explain general and specific literary phenomena, to ground the science of criticism, and to sugges…Read more
  •  93
    Is Hume a naturalist? Does he regard all or nearly all beliefs and actions as rationally unjustified? In order to settle these questions, it is necessary to examine their key terms and to understand the character-especially the normative character-of Hume's philosophical project. This paper argues that Hume is a naturalist-and, in particular, both a moral and an epistemic naturalist-in quite robust ways; and that Hume can properly regard many actions and beliefs as "rationally justified" in seve…Read more
  •  43
    Priority and Separability in Hume’s Empiricism
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 67 (3): 270-288. 1985.
  •  20
    Modalities (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 48 (3): 668-669. 1995.
  •  23
    The Cambridge companion to Spinoza (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1996.
    Benedict (Baruch) de Spinoza (1632–1677) was one of the most systematic, inspiring, and influential philosophers of the early modern period. From a pantheistic starting point that identified God with Nature as all of reality, he sought to demonstrate an ethics of reason, virtue, and freedom while unifying religion with science and mind with body. His contributions to metaphysics, epistemology, psychology, ethics, politics, and the analysis of religion remain vital to the present day. Yet his wri…Read more
  •  23
    Spinoza's Conatus Argument
    In Olli Koistinen & John Ivan Biro (eds.), Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes, Oup Usa. pp. 127-58. 2002.
  •  65
    Replies (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (1). 2001.
    David Owen begins his contribution by setting out very clearly how my interpretation of Hume’s distinction between simple and complex perceptions helps to resolve some puzzles about apparent counterexamples to the two most fundamental principles of Hume’s cognitive psychology: the Copy Principle and the Separability Principle. His primary object of criticism is my interpretation of Hume’s famous conclusion that inductive inferences are “not determin’d by reason”. I am as grateful for Owen’s crit…Read more
  •  34
    Aaron V. Garrett, Meaning in Spinoza's Method (review)
    Philosophical Review 118 (2): 241-244. 2009.
  •  70
    Leibniz, God, and Necessity
    Philosophical Review 123 (2): 234-238. 2014.
    Book Review of Leibniz, God, and Necessity by Michael Griffin
  •  6
    Truth, Method, and Correspondence in Spinoza and Leibniz in Spinoza and Leibniz
    Studia Spinozana: An International and Interdisciplinary Series 6 13-43. 1990.
  •  111
    Difficult times for Humean identity? (review)
    Philosophical Studies 146 (3). 2009.
  •  6
    'A Small Tincture of Pyrrhonism': Skepticism and Naturalism in Hume's Science of Man
    In Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian skepticism, Oxford University Press. pp. 68--98. 2004.
  •  31
    Spinoza
    with R. J. Delahunty
    Philosophical Review 96 (4): 610. 1987.
  •  36
    In a 1998 Hume Studies book symposium, Peter Millican provided excellent critical comments on my Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy, and I am grateful that he has done the same for Hume. Many of the new or revised interpretations in the latter book result, directly or indirectly, from his extraordinary stimulus, both in his writings and in person, as a philosophical scholar and interlocutor. His comments range over much of the book, but the majority of them concern chapter 2, chapter …Read more
  •  31
    This chapter contains section titled: Some Features of Hume's Approach to the Science of Man Structure and Content of “Conclusion of this book” The Rational Justification of Belief Skepticism and Naturalism Notes References Further reading.
  •  193
    The First Motive to Justice: Hume's Circle Argument Squared
    Hume Studies 33 (2): 257-288. 2007.
    Hume argues that respect for property (“justice”) is a convention-dependent (“artificial”) virtue. He does so by appeal to a principle, derived from his virtue-based approach to ethics, which requires that, for any kind of virtuous action, there be a “first virtuous motive” that is other than a sense of moral duty. It has been objected, however, that in the case of justice (and also in a parallel argument concerning promise-keeping) Hume (i) does not, (ii) should not, and (iii) cannot recognize …Read more