•  32
    It is an honor to receive such extensive comments from Louis Loeb, whose work I admire and from whom I have learned much. In particular, his landmark 2002 book, Stability and Justification in Hume’s “Treatise” and his 2010 collection of essays, Reflection and the Stability of Belief: Essays on Descartes, Hume, and Reid are essential reading for anyone who wants to understand early modern epistemology. Some of what I have learned from him is reflected in the book on which he is now commenting whi…Read more
  •  149
    What's True about Hume's 'True Religion'?
    Journal of Scottish Philosophy 10 (2): 199-220. 2012.
    Despite his well-known criticisms of popular religion, Hume refers in seemingly complimentary terms to ‘true religion’; in Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, his character Philo goes so far as to express ‘veneration for’ it. This paper addresses three questions. First, did Hume himself really approve of something that he called ‘true religion’? Second, what did he mean by calling it ‘true’? Third, what did he take it to be? By appeal to some of his key doctrines about causation and probabili…Read more
  •  39
    Hume
    Routledge. 2015.
    Beginning with an overview of Hume's life and work, Don Garrett introduces in clear and accessible style the central aspects of Hume's thought. These include Hume's lifelong exploration of the human mind; his theories of inductive inference and causation; skepticism and personal identity; moral and political philosophy; aesthetics; and philosophy of religion. The final chapter considers the influence and legacy of Hume's thought today. Throughout, Garrett draws on and explains many of Hume's cen…Read more
  •  51
    Spinoza: The Enduring Questions (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (3): 460-461. 1996.
    460 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 34:3 JULY 1996 Graeme Hunter, editor. Spinoza: The Enduring Questions. Toronto: University of To- ronto Press, 1994. Pp. xi + 182. Cloth, $70.00. This volume of eight essays is dedicated to the memory of the late David Savan, and originated from a conference held in his honor prior to his untimely death. The lead essay is by Savan himself, and most of the other essays acknowledge the influence of his work. The first three essays address not only an "endur…Read more
  •  23
    Spinoza, by Alan Donagan (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4): 952-955. 1991.
  • Benedict de Spinoza, Ethics (1677)
    In Jorge J. E. Gracia, Gregory M. Reichberg & Bernard N. Schumacher (eds.), The Classics of Western Philosophy: A Reader's Guide, Wiley-blackwell. pp. 245. 2003.
  •  15
    Part of Nature: Self-Knowledge in Spinoza's "Ethics" (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 34 (2): 299-301. 1996.
    BOOK REVIEWS ~99 edge of Hebrew and Hebrew texts, from encounters with Iberian Jews, and from polemical Christian concerns. The changing situation within German Christendom greatly influenced the way Jews, their history, and their customs were seen. Arthur Williamson, an expert in Scottish intellectual history, treats a somewhat amazing phenomenon: the Scots from the Reformation onward saw themselves as Jews, and developed a Judaized political history. From sometime in the late Middle Ages, the …Read more
  •  19
    Mind and Morality (review)
    Philosophical Review 110 (1): 132-134. 2001.
    In the introduction to his Mind and Morality: An Examination of Hume’s Moral Psychology, John Bricke traces the remarkable lack of agreement among commentators concerning the nature of Hume’s moral philosophy to two main failings: insufficient attention to “the foundations, in his philosophy of mind, on which Hume builds when constructing his theory of morality” and “the practice of taking his theory of morality as a patchwork of severally brilliant and provocative, but essentially unintegrated …Read more
  •  197
    Hume's self-doubts about personal identity
    Philosophical Review 90 (3): 337-358. 1981.
    In this appendix to "a treatise of human nature", Hume expresses dissatisfaction with his own account of personal identity, Claiming that it is "inconsistent." in spite of much recent discussion of the appendix, There has been little agreement either about the reasons for hume's second thoughts or about the philosophical moral to be drawn from them. The present article argues, First, That none of the explanations for his misgivings which have been offered has succeeded in describing a problem wh…Read more
  •  1
    Truth, method, and correspondence in Spinoza and Leibniz
    Studia Spinozana: An International and Interdisciplinary Series 6 (n/a): 13. 1990.
  •  231
    Spinoza's "ontological" argument
    Philosophical Review 88 (2): 198-223. 1979.
    I argue that spinoza's ontological argument is successful when it is understood to have two premises: (i) it is possible for god to exist, (ii) it is necessary that, if god exists, he necessarily does. the argument is valid in s5. spinoza is in a position to establish the second premise of the argument on the basis of his definitions and axioms. the first premise was assumed to be true, but, as leibniz noted, it must be established for the conclusion of the argument to be forthcoming. this is on…Read more
  •  15
    Chapter 10. Should Hume Have Been a Transcendental Idealist?
    In Daniel Garber & Béatrice Longuenesse (eds.), Kant and the Early Moderns, Princeton University Press. pp. 193-208. 2008.
  •  360
    Is Hume a naturalist? Does he regard all or nearly all beliefs and actions as rationally unjustified? In order to settle these questions, it is necessary to examine their key terms and to understand the character-especially the normative character-of Hume's philosophical project. This paper argues that Hume is a naturalist-and, in particular, both a moral and an epistemic naturalist-in quite robust ways; and that Hume can properly regard many actions and beliefs as "rationally justified" in seve…Read more
  •  37
    The literary arts in Hume's science of the fancy
    Kriterion: Journal of Philosophy 44 (108): 161-179. 2003.
    Philosophers have long disagreed about whether poetry, drama, and other literary arts are important to philosophy and among those who believe that they are important, explanations of that importance have differed greatly. This paper aims to explain and illustrate some of the reasons why Hume found literature to be an important topic for philosophy and philosophers. Philosophy, he holds, can help to explain general and specific literary phenomena, to ground the science of criticism, and to sugges…Read more
  •  43
    Priority and Separability in Hume’s Empiricism
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 67 (3): 270-288. 1985.
  •  20
    Modalities (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 48 (3): 668-669. 1995.
  •  23
    The Cambridge companion to Spinoza (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 1996.
    Benedict (Baruch) de Spinoza (1632–1677) was one of the most systematic, inspiring, and influential philosophers of the early modern period. From a pantheistic starting point that identified God with Nature as all of reality, he sought to demonstrate an ethics of reason, virtue, and freedom while unifying religion with science and mind with body. His contributions to metaphysics, epistemology, psychology, ethics, politics, and the analysis of religion remain vital to the present day. Yet his wri…Read more
  •  23
    Spinoza's Conatus Argument
    In Olli Koistinen & J. I. Biro (eds.), Spinoza: Metaphysical Themes, Oxford University Press. pp. 127-58. 2002.
  •  64
    Replies (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (1). 2001.
    David Owen begins his contribution by setting out very clearly how my interpretation of Hume’s distinction between simple and complex perceptions helps to resolve some puzzles about apparent counterexamples to the two most fundamental principles of Hume’s cognitive psychology: the Copy Principle and the Separability Principle. His primary object of criticism is my interpretation of Hume’s famous conclusion that inductive inferences are “not determin’d by reason”. I am as grateful for Owen’s crit…Read more
  •  32
    Aaron V. Garrett, Meaning in Spinoza's Method (review)
    Philosophical Review 118 (2): 241-244. 2009.
  •  69
    Leibniz, God, and Necessity
    Philosophical Review 123 (2): 234-238. 2014.
    Book Review of Leibniz, God, and Necessity by Michael Griffin
  •  6
    Truth, Method, and Correspondence in Spinoza and Leibniz in Spinoza and Leibniz
    Studia Spinozana: An International and Interdisciplinary Series 6 13-43. 1990.
  •  108
    Difficult times for Humean identity? (review)
    Philosophical Studies 146 (3). 2009.
  •  29
    Spinoza
    with R. J. Delahunty
    Philosophical Review 96 (4): 610. 1987.
  •  6
    'A Small Tincture of Pyrrhonism': Skepticism and Naturalism in Hume's Science of Man
    In Walter Sinnott-Armstrong (ed.), Pyrrhonian Skepticism, Oxford University Press. pp. 68--98. 2004.