•  116
    Principles of reflection and second-order logic
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 16 (3). 1987.
  •  37
    Comparing implicit and explicit memory for brand names from advertisements
    with H. Shanker Krishnan
    Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 2 (2): 147. 1996.
  •  290
    Epistemology of mathematics: What are the questions? What count as answers?
    Philosophical Quarterly 61 (242): 130-150. 2011.
    A paper in this journal by Fraser MacBride, ‘Can Ante Rem Structuralism Solve the Access Problem?’, raises important issues concerning the epistemological goals and burdens of contemporary philosophy of mathematics, and perhaps philosophy of science and other disciplines as well. I use a response to MacBride's paper as a framework for developing a broadly holistic framework for these issues, and I attempt to steer a middle course between reductive foundationalism and extreme naturalistic quietis…Read more
  •  44
    On the notion of effectiveness
    History and Philosophy of Logic 1 (1-2): 209-230. 1980.
    This paper focuses on two notions of effectiveness which are not treated in detail elsewhere. Unlike the standard computability notion, which is a property of functions themselves, both notions of effectiveness are properties of interpreted linguistic presentations of functions. It is shown that effectiveness is epistemically at least as basic as computability in the sense that decisions about computability normally involve judgments concerning effectiveness. There are many occurrences of the pr…Read more
  •  148
    ‘Neo-logicist‘ logic is not epistemically innocent
    with Alan Weir
    Philosophia Mathematica 8 (2): 160--189. 2000.
    The neo-logicist argues tliat standard mathematics can be derived by purely logical means from abstraction principles—such as Hume's Principle— which are held to lie 'epistcmically innocent'. We show that the second-order axiom of comprehension applied to non-instantiated properties and the standard first-order existential instantiation and universal elimination principles are essential for the derivation of key results, specifically a theorem of infinity, but have not been shown to be epistemic…Read more
  •  3
  •  131
    Mathematics and philosophy of mathematics
    Philosophia Mathematica 2 (2): 148-160. 1994.
    The purpose of this note is to examine the relationship between the practice of mathematics and the philosophy of mathematics, ontology in particular. One conclusion is that the enterprises are (or should be) closely related, with neither one dominating the other. One cannot 'read off' the correct way to do mathematics from the true ontology, for example, nor can one ‘read off’ the true ontology from mathematics as practiced.
  •  138
  •  174
    Vagueness in context
    Oxford University Press. 2006.
    Stewart Shapiro's ambition in Vagueness in Context is to develop a comprehensive account of the meaning, function, and logic of vague terms in an idealized version of a natural language like English. It is a commonplace that the extensions of vague terms vary according to their context: a person can be tall with respect to male accountants and not tall (even short) with respect to professional basketball players. The key feature of Shapiro's account is that the extensions of vague terms also var…Read more
  •  138
    This chapter provides broad coverage of the notion of logical consequence, exploring its modal, semantic, and epistemic aspects. It develops the contrast between proof-theoretic notion of consequence, in terms of deduction, and a model-theoretic approach, in terms of truth-conditions. The main purpose is to relate the formal, technical work in logic to the philosophical concepts that underlie reasoning.
  •  146
    Reasoning with Slippery Predicates
    Studia Logica 90 (3): 313-336. 2008.
    It is a commonplace that the extensions of most, perhaps all, vague predicates vary with such features as comparison class and paradigm and contrasting cases. My view proposes another, more pervasive contextual parameter. Vague predicates exhibit what I call open texture: in some circumstances, competent speakers can go either way in the borderline region. The shifting extension and anti-extensions of vague predicates are tracked by what David Lewis calls the “conversational score”, and are regu…Read more
  •  4
    Book Reviews (review)
    Mind 101 (402): 361-364. 1992.
  •  63
    The status of logic
    In Paul Artin Boghossian & Christopher Peacocke (eds.), New Essays on the A Priori, Oxford University Press. pp. 333--366. 2000.
  •  59
    Intentional mathematics (edited book)
    Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada, Elsevier Science Pub. Co.. 1985.
    Among the aims of this book are: - The discussion of some important philosophical issues using the precision of mathematics. - The development of formal systems that contain both classical and constructive components. This allows the study of constructivity in otherwise classical contexts and represents the formalization of important intensional aspects of mathematical practice. - The direct formalization of intensional concepts (such as computability) in a mixed constructive/classical context.
  •  18
    Reflections on Kurt Godel
    Philosophical Review 100 (1): 130. 1991.
  • Anti-realism and modality
    In J. Czermak (ed.), Philosophy of Mathematics, Hölder-pichler-tempsky. pp. 269--287. 1993.
  •  199
    The central contention of this book is that second-order logic has a central role to play in laying the foundations of mathematics. In order to develop the argument fully, the author presents a detailed description of higher-order logic, including a comprehensive discussion of its semantics. He goes on to demonstrate the prevalence of second-order concepts in mathematics and the extent to which mathematical ideas can be formulated in higher-order logic. He also shows how first-order languages ar…Read more
  • Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure and Ontology
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198): 120-123. 2000.
  •  217
    Do not claim too much: Second-order logic and first-order logic
    Philosophia Mathematica 7 (1): 42-64. 1999.
    The purpose of this article is to delimit what can and cannot be claimed on behalf of second-order logic. The starting point is some of the discussions surrounding my Foundations without Foundationalism: A Case for Secondorder Logic.
  •  210
    Mathematical structuralism
    Philosophia Mathematica 4 (2): 81-82. 1996.
    STEWART SHAPIRO; Mathematical Structuralism, Philosophia Mathematica, Volume 4, Issue 2, 1 May 1996, Pages 81–82, https://doi.org/10.1093/philmat/4.2.81.
  •  2
    Simple truth, contradiction, and consistency
    In Graham Priest, J. C. Beall & Bradley Armour-Garb (eds.), The Law of Non-Contradiction, Oxford University Press. 2004.
  •  80
    Classical Logic
    In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, The Metaphysics Research Lab. 2014.
    Typically, a logic consists of a formal or informal language together with a deductive system and/or a model-theoretic semantics. The language is, or corresponds to, a part of a natural language like English or Greek. The deductive system is to capture, codify, or simply record which inferences are correct for the given language, and the semantics is to capture, codify, or record the meanings, or truth-conditions, or possible truth conditions, for at least part of the language.