•  1
  •  21
    Vagueness and Logic
    In Giuseppina Ronzitti (ed.), Vagueness: A Guide, Springer Verlag. pp. 55--81. 2011.
  •  276
    The Objectivity of Mathematics
    Synthese 156 (2): 337-381. 2007.
    The purpose of this paper is to apply Crispin Wright’s criteria and various axes of objectivity to mathematics. I test the criteria and the objectivity of mathematics against each other. Along the way, various issues concerning general logic and epistemology are encountered.
  •  344
    Identity, indiscernibility, and Ante Rem structuralism: The tale of I and –I
    Philosophia Mathematica 16 (3): 285-309. 2008.
    Some authors have claimed that ante rem structuralism has problems with structures that have indiscernible places. In response, I argue that there is no requirement that mathematical objects be individuated in a non-trivial way. Metaphysical principles and intuitions to the contrary do not stand up to ordinary mathematical practice, which presupposes an identity relation that, in a sense, cannot be defined. In complex analysis, the two square roots of –1 are indiscernible: anything true of one o…Read more
  •  88
    Reasoning, logic and computation
    Philosophia Mathematica 3 (1): 31-51. 1995.
    The idea that logic and reasoning are somehow related goes back to antiquity. It clearly underlies much of the work in logic, as witnessed by the development of computability, and formal and mechanical deductive systems, for example. On the other hand, a platitude is that logic is the study of correct reasoning; and reasoning is cognitive if anything Is. Thus, the relationship between logic, computation, and correct reasoning makes an interesting and historically central case study for mechanism…Read more
  •  76
    Book reviews (review)
    with Ben-Ami Scharfstein, Gary Jason, John Blackmore, R. A. Naulty, and F. Bradford Wallack
    Philosophia 17 (4): 551-570. 1987.
  •  192
    Truth, function and paradox
    Analysis 71 (1): 38-44. 2011.
    Michael Lynch’s Truth as One and Many is a contribution to the large body of philosophical literature on the nature of truth. Within that genre, advocates of truth-as-correspondence, advocates of truth-as-coherence, and the like, all hold that truth has a single underlying metaphysical nature, but they sharply disagree as to what this nature is. Lynch argues that many of these views make good sense of truth attributions for a limited stretch of discourse, but he adds that each of the contenders …Read more
  •  175
    Frege Meets Zermelo: A Perspective on Ineffability and Reflection
    Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (2): 241-266. 2008.
    1. Philosophical background: iteration, ineffability, reflection. There are at least two heuristic motivations for the axioms of standard set theory, by which we mean, as usual, first-order Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC): the iterative conception and limitation of size (see Boolos, 1989). Each strand provides a rather hospitable environment for the hypothesis that the set-theoretic universe is ineffable, which is our target in this paper, although the motivation is di…Read more
  •  84
    The Nature and Limits of Abstraction (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 54 (214). 2004.
    This article is an extended critical study of Kit Fine’s The limits of abstraction, which is a sustained attempt to take the measure of the neo-logicist program in the philosophy and foundations of mathematics, founded on abstraction principles like Hume’s principle. The present article covers the philosophical and technical aspects of Fine’s deep and penetrating study.
  •  36
    Priest, Graham. An Introduction to Non-classical Logic (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 56 (3): 670-672. 2003.
  •  11
    Mathematics Without Numbers (review)
    Noûs 27 (4): 522-525. 1993.
  •  39
    Acceptable notation
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 23 (1): 14-20. 1982.
  •  12
    Matftematical Objects
    In Bonnie Gold & Roger Simons (eds.), Proof and Other Dilemmas: Mathematics and Philosophy, Mathematical Association of America. pp. 157. 2008.
  •  102
    Space, number and structure: A tale of two debates
    Philosophia Mathematica 4 (2): 148-173. 1996.
    Around the turn of the century, Poincare and Hilbert each published an account of geometry that took the discipline to be an implicit definition of its concepts. The terms ‘point’, ‘line’, and ‘plane’ can be applied to any system of objects that satisfies the axioms. Each mathematician found spirited opposition from a different logicist—Russell against Poincare' and Frege against Hilbert— who maintained the dying view that geometry essentially concerns space or spatial intuition. The debates ill…Read more
  •  225
    Conservativeness and incompleteness
    Journal of Philosophy 80 (9): 521-531. 1983.
  •  90
    Vagueness, Open-Texture, and Retrievability
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 56 (2-3): 307-326. 2013.
    Just about every theorist holds that vague terms are context-sensitive to some extent. What counts as ?tall?, ?rich?, and ?bald? depends on the ambient comparison class, paradigm cases, and/or the like. To take a stock example, a given person might be tall with respect to European entrepreneurs and downright short with respect to professional basketball players. It is also generally agreed that vagueness remains even after comparison class, paradigm cases, etc. are fixed, and so this context sen…Read more
  •  51
    Life on the Ship of Neurath: Mathematics in the Philosophy of Mathematics
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 26 (2): 11--27. 2012.
    Some central philosophical issues concern the use of mathematics in putatively non-mathematical endeavors. One such endeavor, of course, is philosophy, and the philosophy of mathematics is a key instance of that. The present article provides an idiosyncratic survey of the use of mathematical results to provide support or counter-support to various philosophical programs concerning the foundations of mathematics
  •  141
    Structures and Logics: A Case for (a) Relativism
    Erkenntnis 79 (S2): 309-329. 2014.
    In this paper, I use the cases of intuitionistic arithmetic with Church’s thesis, intuitionistic analysis, and smooth infinitesimal analysis to argue for a sort of pluralism or relativism about logic. The thesis is that logic is relative to a structure. There are classical structures, intuitionistic structures, and (possibly) paraconsistent structures. Each such structure is a legitimate branch of mathematics, and there does not seem to be an interesting logic that is common to all of them. One …Read more
  •  97
    Understanding church's thesis
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 10 (3): 353--65. 1981.
  •  27
    I—Stewart Shapiro
    Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79 (1): 147-165. 2005.
  •  18
    Review: Sets and Abstracts: Discussion (review)
    Philosophical Studies 122 (3). 2005.
  •  14
    Arithmetic Sinn and Effectiveness
    Dialectica 38 (1): 3-16. 1984.
    SummaryAccording to Dummett's understanding of Frege, the sense of a denoting expression is a procedure for determining its denotation. The purpose of this article is to pursue this suggestion and develop a semi‐formal interpretation of Fregean sense for the special case of a first‐order language of arithmetic. In particular, we define the sense of each arithmetic expression to be a hypothetical process to determine the denoted number or truth value. The sense‐process is “hypothetical” in that t…Read more
  •  128
    The purpose of this paper is to present a thought experiment and argument that spells trouble for “radical” deflationism concerning meaning and truth such as that advocated by the staunch nominalist Hartry Field. The thought experiment does not sit well with any view that limits a truth predicate to sentences understood by a given speaker or to sentences in (or translatable into) a given language, unless that language is universal. The scenario in question concerns sentences that are not under…Read more
  •  116
    Principles of reflection and second-order logic
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 16 (3). 1987.
  •  37
    Comparing implicit and explicit memory for brand names from advertisements
    with H. Shanker Krishnan
    Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied 2 (2): 147. 1996.
  •  3