•  970
    What is mathematical logic?
    Philosophia 8 (1): 79-94. 1978.
    This review concludes that if the authors know what mathematical logic is they have not shared their knowledge with the readers. This highly praised book is replete with errors and incoherency.
  • Thinking about Mathematics: The Philosophy of Mathematics
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (207): 272-274. 2002.
  •  156
    Frege Meets Aristotle: Points as Abstracts
    Philosophia Mathematica. 2015.
    There are a number of regions-based accounts of space/time, due to Whitehead, Roeper, Menger, Tarski, the present authors, and others. They all follow the Aristotelian theme that continua are not composed of points: each region has a proper part. The purpose of this note is to show how to recapture ‘points’ in such frameworks via Scottish neo-logicist abstraction principles. The results recapitulate some Aristotelian themes. A second agenda is to provide a new arena to help decide what is at sta…Read more
  •  56
    Remarks on the development of computability
    History and Philosophy of Logic 4 (1-2): 203-220. 1983.
    The purpose of this article is to examine aspects of the development of the concept and theory of computability through the theory of recursive functions. Following a brief introduction, Section 2 is devoted to the presuppositions of computability. It focuses on certain concepts, beliefs and theorems necessary for a general property of computability to be formulated and developed into a mathematical theory. The following two sections concern situations in which the presuppositions were realized …Read more
  •  88
    Second-order logic, foundations, and rules
    Journal of Philosophy 87 (5): 234-261. 1990.
  •  237
    There is a parallel between the debate between Gottlob Frege and David Hilbert at the turn of the twentieth century and at least some aspects of the current controversy over whether category theory provides the proper framework for structuralism in the philosophy of mathematics. The main issue, I think, concerns the place and interpretation of meta-mathematics in an algebraic or structuralist approach to mathematics. Can meta-mathematics itself be understood in algebraic or structural terms? Or …Read more
  •  418
    Mathematics and reality
    Philosophy of Science 50 (4): 523-548. 1983.
    The subject of this paper is the philosophical problem of accounting for the relationship between mathematics and non-mathematical reality. The first section, devoted to the importance of the problem, suggests that many of the reasons for engaging in philosophy at all make an account of the relationship between mathematics and reality a priority, not only in philosophy of mathematics and philosophy of science, but also in general epistemology/metaphysics. This is followed by a (rather brief) sur…Read more
  •  103
    Sets and Abstracts – Discussion
    Philosophical Studies 122 (3): 315-332. 2005.
  •  50
    Vagueness in Context
    Oxford University Press UK. 2006.
    Stewart Shapiro's aim in Vagueness in Context is to develop both a philosophical and a formal, model-theoretic account of the meaning, function, and logic of vague terms in an idealized version of a natural language like English. It is a commonplace that the extensions of vague terms vary with such contextual factors as the comparison class and paradigm cases. A person can be tall with respect to male accountants and not tall with respect to professional basketball players. The main feature of S…Read more
  •  54
    Review of Michael P. Lynch, Truth as One and Many (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2009 (9). 2009.
  •  132
    Author index — volume 7
    Philosophia Mathematica 7 (3): 351-352. 1999.
  •  126
    Tarski’s Theorem and the Extensionality of Truth
    Erkenntnis 78 (5): 1197-1204. 2013.
  •  1
    Intensional Mathematics
    Philosophy of Science 56 (1): 177-178. 1989.
  •  222
    Philosophy of mathematics: structure and ontology
    Oxford University Press. 1997.
    Do numbers, sets, and so forth, exist? What do mathematical statements mean? Are they literally true or false, or do they lack truth values altogether? Addressing questions that have attracted lively debate in recent years, Stewart Shapiro contends that standard realist and antirealist accounts of mathematics are both problematic. As Benacerraf first noted, we are confronted with the following powerful dilemma. The desired continuity between mathematical and, say, scientific language suggests re…Read more
  •  82
    The George Boolos memorial symposium II
    Philosophia Mathematica 9 (1): 3-4. 2001.
  •  228
    Higher-Order Logic or Set Theory: A False Dilemma
    Philosophia Mathematica 20 (3): 305-323. 2012.
    The purpose of this article is show that second-order logic, as understood through standard semantics, is intimately bound up with set theory, or some other general theory of interpretations, structures, or whatever. Contra Quine, this does not disqualify second-order logic from its role in foundational studies. To wax Quinean, why should there be a sharp border separating mathematics from logic, especially the logic of mathematics?
  •  56
    Turing projectability
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (4): 520-535. 1987.
  •  21
    Book reviews (review)
    with Timo Airaksinen and W. Stephen Croddy
    Philosophia 14 (3-4): 427-467. 1984.
  •  182
    So truth is safe from paradox: now what?
    Philosophical Studies 147 (3): 445-455. 2010.
    The article is part of a symposium on Hartry Field’s “Saving truth from paradox”. The book is one of the most significant intellectual achievements of the past decades, but it is not clear what, exactly, it accomplishes. I explore some alternatives, relating the developed view to the intuitive, pre-theoretic notion of truth.
  •  16
    Do Not Claim Too Much: Second-order Logic and First-order Logic
    Philosophia Mathematica 6 (3): 42-64. 1998.
    The purpose of this article is to delimit what can and cannot be claimed on behalf of second-order logic. The starting point is some of the discussions surrounding my Foundations without Foundationalism: A Case for Secondorder Logic.
  •  15
    Essay Review
    History and Philosophy of Logic 6 (1): 215-221. 1985.
    D. GABBAY and F. GUENTHNER (eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic. Volume 1: Elements of classical logic. Dordrecht, Boston, and Lancaster: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1983. xiv + 497 pp. Dfl225/$98.00
  •  198
  •  9
    Structure and Ontology
    Philosophical Topics 17 (2): 145-171. 1989.
  •  6
    A typical interpreted formal language has (first‐order) variables that range over a collection of objects, sometimes called a domain‐of‐discourse. The domain is what the formal language is about. A language may also contain second‐order variables that range over properties, sets, or relations on the items in the domain‐of‐discourse, or over functions from the domain to itself. For example, the sentence ‘Alexander has all the qualities of a great leader’ would naturally be rendered with a second‐…Read more
  •  111
    Famously, Michael Dummett argues that considerations concerning the role of language in communication lead to the rejection of classical logic in favor of intuitionistic logic. Potentially, this results in massive revisions of established mathematics. Recently, Neil Tennant (“The law of excluded middle is synthetic a priori, if valid”, Philosophical Topics 24 (1996), 205-229) suggested that a Dummettian anti-realist can accept the law of excluded middle as a synthetic, a priori principle groun…Read more
  •  203
    Modality and ontology
    Mind 102 (407): 455-481. 1993.