•  21
  •  147
    Victor vanquished
    Analysis 62 (2). 2002.
    The naive anti-realist holds the following principle: (◊K) All truths are knowable. This unrestricted generalization (◊K), as is now well known, falls prey to Fitch’s Paradox (Fitch 1963: 38, Theorem 1). It can be used as the only suspect principle, alongside others that cannot be impugned, to prove quite generally, and constructively, that the set {p, ¬Kp} is inconsistent (Tennant 1997: 261). From this it would follow, intuitionistically, that any proposition that is never actually known to be …Read more
  •  11
    On having bad contractions, or: no room for recovery
    Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logics 7 (1-2): 241-266. 1997.
    ABSTRACT The well-known AGM-theory-contraction and theory-revision, due to Alchourrón, Gärdenfors and Makinson, relies heavily on the so-called postulate of recovery. This postulate is supposed to capture the requirement of “minimum mutilation”; but it does not. Recovery can be satisfied even when there is more mutilation than is necessary. Recovery also ensures that very often too little is given up in a contraction, in this paper I bring out clearly the deficiencies of the AGM-theory in these …Read more
  •  18
  •  61
    We present a logically detailed case-study of Darwinian evolutionary explanation. Special features of Darwin’s explanatory schema made it an unusual theoretical breakthrough, from the point of view of the philosophy of science. The schema employs no theoretical terms, and puts forward no theoretical hypotheses. Instead, it uses three observational generalizations—Variability, Heritability and Differential Reproduction—along with an innocuous assumption of Causal Efficacy, to derive Adaptive Evol…Read more
  •  68
    Frege's content-principle and relevant deducibility
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (3): 245-258. 2003.
    Given the harmony principle for logical operators, compositionality ought to ensure that harmony should obtain at the level of whole contents. That is, the role of a content qua premise ought to be balanced exactly by its role as a conclusion. Frege's contextual definition of propositional content happens to exploit this balance, and one appeals to the Cut rule to show that the definition is adequate. We show here that Frege's definition remains adequate even when one relevantizes logic by aband…Read more
  •  14
    Naturalism in Mathematics (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 35 (4): 351-352. 2003.
  •  53
    Critical Studies / Book Reviews (review)
    Philosophia Mathematica 6 (1): 90-90. 1998.
    The over-arching theme is that we can redeem Frege's key philosophical insights concerning (natural and real) numbers and our knowledge of them, despite Russell's famous discovery of paradox in Frege's own theory of classes. That paradox notwithstanding, numbers are still logical objects, in some sense created or generated by methods or principles of abstraction— which of course cannot be as ambitious as Frege's Basic Law U. These principles not only bring numbers into existence, as it we…Read more
  •  16
    Peacocke argues for a ‘generalized rationalism’, holding that ‘all entitlement has a fundamentally a priori component.’ (2) But his rationalism ‘differs from those of Frege and Gödel, just as theirs differ from that of Leibniz.’ He requires both substantive theories of intentional content and of understanding, and systematic formal theories of referential semantics and truth. We need an externalist theory of content: ‘Only mental states with externally individuated contents can make judgements a…Read more
  •  72
    Logic, Mathematics, and the A Priori, Part I: A Problem for Realism
    Philosophia Mathematica 22 (3): 308-320. 2014.
    This is Part I of a two-part study of the foundations of mathematics through the lenses of (i) apriority and analyticity, and (ii) the resources supplied by Core Logic. Here we explain what is meant by apriority, as the notion applies to knowledge and possibly also to truths in general. We distinguish grounds for knowledge from grounds of truth, in light of our recent work on truthmakers. We then examine the role of apriority in the realism/anti-realism debate. We raise a hitherto unnoticed prob…Read more
  •  91
    A general theory of abstraction operators
    Philosophical Quarterly 54 (214): 105-133. 2004.
    I present a general theory of abstraction operators which treats them as variable-binding term- forming operators, and provides a reasonably uniform treatment for definite descriptions, set abstracts, natural number abstraction, and real number abstraction. This minimizing, extensional and relational theory reveals a striking similarity between definite descriptions and set abstracts, and provides a clear rationale for the claim that there is a logic of sets (which is ontologically non- committa…Read more
  •  346
    Changing the theory of theory change: Reply to my critics
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (4): 569-586. 1997.
    Changing the Theory of Theory Change: Towards a Computational Approach’ (Tennant [1994]; henceforth CTTC) claimed that the AGM postulate of recovery is false, and that AGM contractions of theories can be more than minimally mutilating. It also described an alternative, computational method for contracting theories, called the Staining Algorithm. Makinson [1995] and Hansson and Rott [1995] criticized CTTC's arguments against AGM-theory, and its specific proposals for an alternative, computational…Read more
  •  107
    Is This a Proof I See before Me?
    Analysis 41 (3). 1980.
  •  42
    Rule-Irredundancy and the Sequent Calculus for Core Logic
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (1): 105-125. 2016.
    We explore the consequences, for logical system-building, of taking seriously the aim of having irredundant rules of inference, and a preference for proofs of stronger results over proofs of weaker ones. This leads one to reconsider the structural rules of REFLEXIVITY, THINNING, and CUT. REFLEXIVITY survives in the minimally necessary form $\varphi:\varphi$. Proofs have to get started. CUT is subject to a CUT-elimination theorem, to the effect that one can always make do without applications of …Read more
  •  62
    Introduction
    Philosophia Mathematica 16 (1): 1-3. 2008.
    Christopher Peacocke, in A Study of Concepts, motivates his account of possession conditions for concepts by means of an alleged parallel with the conditions under which numbers are abshacted to give the numerosity of a predicate. There are, however, logical mistakes in Peacocke's treatment of numbers, which undermine his intended analogy. Nevertheless Peacocke's account of possession conditions for concepts is not rendered inadequate simply by virtue of being deprived of the intended analogy an…Read more
  •  45
    Anti-realism and Logic. Truth as Eternal
    with W. D. Hart
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4): 1485. 1989.
  •  50
    Proof and Paradox
    Dialectica 36 (2‐3): 265-296. 1982.
  •  40
    Contracting Intuitionistic Theories
    Studia Logica 80 (2-3): 369-391. 2005.
    I reformulate the AGM-account of contraction (which would yield an account also of revision). The reformulation involves using introduction and elimination rules for relational notions. Then I investigate the extent to which the two main methods of partial meet contraction and safe contraction can be employed for theories closed under intuitionistic consequence.
  •  37
    The relevance of premises to conclusions of core proofs
    Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (4): 743-784. 2015.
  •  9
    On and exist
    Analysis 40 (1): 5-7. 1980.
  • Book Reviews (review)
    Philosophia Mathematica 3 (2): 179-207. 1995.
  •  12
    The future with cloning
    In James H. Fetzer (ed.), Consciousness Evolving, John Benjamins. pp. 34--223. 2002.
  • Editor's Page: Editorial
    American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (4). 2006.
  •  72
    Normalizability, cut eliminability and paradox
    Synthese 199 (Suppl 3): 597-616. 2016.
    This is a reply to the considerations advanced by Schroeder-Heister and Tranchini as prima facie problematic for the proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality, as originally presented in Tennant and subsequently amended in Tennant. Countering these considerations lends new importance to the parallelized forms of elimination rules in natural deduction.