•  68
    Frege's content-principle and relevant deducibility
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 32 (3): 245-258. 2003.
    Given the harmony principle for logical operators, compositionality ought to ensure that harmony should obtain at the level of whole contents. That is, the role of a content qua premise ought to be balanced exactly by its role as a conclusion. Frege's contextual definition of propositional content happens to exploit this balance, and one appeals to the Cut rule to show that the definition is adequate. We show here that Frege's definition remains adequate even when one relevantizes logic by aband…Read more
  •  91
    A general theory of abstraction operators
    Philosophical Quarterly 54 (214): 105-133. 2004.
    I present a general theory of abstraction operators which treats them as variable-binding term- forming operators, and provides a reasonably uniform treatment for definite descriptions, set abstracts, natural number abstraction, and real number abstraction. This minimizing, extensional and relational theory reveals a striking similarity between definite descriptions and set abstracts, and provides a clear rationale for the claim that there is a logic of sets (which is ontologically non- committa…Read more
  •  16
    Peacocke argues for a ‘generalized rationalism’, holding that ‘all entitlement has a fundamentally a priori component.’ (2) But his rationalism ‘differs from those of Frege and Gödel, just as theirs differ from that of Leibniz.’ He requires both substantive theories of intentional content and of understanding, and systematic formal theories of referential semantics and truth. We need an externalist theory of content: ‘Only mental states with externally individuated contents can make judgements a…Read more
  •  72
    Logic, Mathematics, and the A Priori, Part I: A Problem for Realism
    Philosophia Mathematica 22 (3): 308-320. 2014.
    This is Part I of a two-part study of the foundations of mathematics through the lenses of (i) apriority and analyticity, and (ii) the resources supplied by Core Logic. Here we explain what is meant by apriority, as the notion applies to knowledge and possibly also to truths in general. We distinguish grounds for knowledge from grounds of truth, in light of our recent work on truthmakers. We then examine the role of apriority in the realism/anti-realism debate. We raise a hitherto unnoticed prob…Read more
  •  42
    Rule-Irredundancy and the Sequent Calculus for Core Logic
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (1): 105-125. 2016.
    We explore the consequences, for logical system-building, of taking seriously the aim of having irredundant rules of inference, and a preference for proofs of stronger results over proofs of weaker ones. This leads one to reconsider the structural rules of REFLEXIVITY, THINNING, and CUT. REFLEXIVITY survives in the minimally necessary form $\varphi:\varphi$. Proofs have to get started. CUT is subject to a CUT-elimination theorem, to the effect that one can always make do without applications of …Read more
  •  348
    Changing the theory of theory change: Reply to my critics
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (4): 569-586. 1997.
    Changing the Theory of Theory Change: Towards a Computational Approach’ (Tennant [1994]; henceforth CTTC) claimed that the AGM postulate of recovery is false, and that AGM contractions of theories can be more than minimally mutilating. It also described an alternative, computational method for contracting theories, called the Staining Algorithm. Makinson [1995] and Hansson and Rott [1995] criticized CTTC's arguments against AGM-theory, and its specific proposals for an alternative, computational…Read more
  •  107
    Is This a Proof I See before Me?
    Analysis 41 (3). 1980.
  •  50
    Proof and Paradox
    Dialectica 36 (2‐3): 265-296. 1982.
  •  40
    Contracting Intuitionistic Theories
    Studia Logica 80 (2-3): 369-391. 2005.
    I reformulate the AGM-account of contraction (which would yield an account also of revision). The reformulation involves using introduction and elimination rules for relational notions. Then I investigate the extent to which the two main methods of partial meet contraction and safe contraction can be employed for theories closed under intuitionistic consequence.
  •  62
    Introduction
    Philosophia Mathematica 16 (1): 1-3. 2008.
    Christopher Peacocke, in A Study of Concepts, motivates his account of possession conditions for concepts by means of an alleged parallel with the conditions under which numbers are abshacted to give the numerosity of a predicate. There are, however, logical mistakes in Peacocke's treatment of numbers, which undermine his intended analogy. Nevertheless Peacocke's account of possession conditions for concepts is not rendered inadequate simply by virtue of being deprived of the intended analogy an…Read more
  •  45
    Anti-realism and Logic. Truth as Eternal
    with W. D. Hart
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4): 1485. 1989.
  •  9
    On and exist
    Analysis 40 (1): 5-7. 1980.
  • Book Reviews (review)
    Philosophia Mathematica 3 (2): 179-207. 1995.
  •  37
    The relevance of premises to conclusions of core proofs
    Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (4): 743-784. 2015.
  •  1067
    Aristotle’s Syllogistic and Core Logic
    History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (2): 120-147. 2014.
    I use the Corcoran–Smiley interpretation of Aristotle's syllogistic as my starting point for an examination of the syllogistic from the vantage point of modern proof theory. I aim to show that fresh logical insights are afforded by a proof-theoretically more systematic account of all four figures. First I regiment the syllogisms in the Gentzen–Prawitz system of natural deduction, using the universal and existential quantifiers of standard first-order logic, and the usual formalizations of Aristo…Read more
  •  12
    The future with cloning
    In James H. Fetzer (ed.), Consciousness Evolving, John Benjamins. pp. 34--223. 2002.
  • Editor's Page: Editorial
    American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (4). 2006.
  •  72
    Normalizability, cut eliminability and paradox
    Synthese 199 (Suppl 3): 597-616. 2016.
    This is a reply to the considerations advanced by Schroeder-Heister and Tranchini as prima facie problematic for the proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality, as originally presented in Tennant and subsequently amended in Tennant. Countering these considerations lends new importance to the parallelized forms of elimination rules in natural deduction.
  •  87
    Anti-realist aporias
    Mind 109 (436): 825--854. 2000.
    Using a quantified propositional logic involving the operators it is known that and it is possible to know that, we formalize various interesting philosophical claims involved in the realism debate. We set out inferential rules for the epistemic modalities, ranging from ones that are obviously analytic, to ones that are epistemologically more substantive or even controversial. Then we investigate various aporias for the realism debate. These are constructively inconsistent triads of claims from …Read more
  •  26
    Revamping the restriction strategy
    In Joe Salerno (ed.), New Essays on the Knowability Paradox, Oxford University Press. 2009.
    This study continues the anti-realist’s quest for a principled way to avoid Fitch’s paradox. It is proposed that the Cartesian restriction on the anti-realist’s knowability principle ‘ϕ, therefore 3Kϕ’ should be formulated as a consistency requirement not on the premise ϕ of an application of the rule, but rather on the set of assumptions on which the relevant occurrence of ϕ depends. It is stressed, by reference to illustrative proofs, how important it is to have proofs in normal form before ap…Read more
  •  16
    Deflationism and the Godel Phenomena
    Mind 111 (443): 551-582. 2002.
    Any consistent and sufficiently strong system of first-order formal arithmetic fails to decide some independent Gödel sentence. We examine consistent first-order extensions of such systems. Our purpose is to discover what is minimally required by way of such extension in order to be able to prove the Gödel sentence in a non-trivial fashion. The extended methods of formal proof must capture the essentials of the so-called 'semantical argument' for the truth of the Gödel sentence. We are concerned…Read more
  •  93
    Paradoxes of pure curiosity
    Theory and Decision 38 (3): 321-330. 1995.
    We consider how a rational decision theorist would justify committing resources to an investigation designed to satisfy pure curiosity. We derive a strange result about the need to be completely open-minded about the outcome
  •  1
    Philosophy, Evolution & Human Nature
    with Florian von Schilcher
    Synthese 70 (3): 459-462. 1987.
  •  4
    Written for any readers interested in better harnessing philosophy's real value, this book covers a broad range of fundamental philosophical problems and certain intellectual techniques for addressing those problems. In Introducing Philosophy: God, Mind, World, and Logic, Neil Tennant helps any student in pursuit of a 'big picture' to think independently, question received dogma, and analyse problems incisively. It also connects philosophy to other areas of study at the university, enabling all …Read more