•  42
    Rule-Irredundancy and the Sequent Calculus for Core Logic
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 57 (1): 105-125. 2016.
    We explore the consequences, for logical system-building, of taking seriously the aim of having irredundant rules of inference, and a preference for proofs of stronger results over proofs of weaker ones. This leads one to reconsider the structural rules of REFLEXIVITY, THINNING, and CUT. REFLEXIVITY survives in the minimally necessary form $\varphi:\varphi$. Proofs have to get started. CUT is subject to a CUT-elimination theorem, to the effect that one can always make do without applications of …Read more
  •  62
    Introduction
    Philosophia Mathematica 16 (1): 1-3. 2008.
    Christopher Peacocke, in A Study of Concepts, motivates his account of possession conditions for concepts by means of an alleged parallel with the conditions under which numbers are abshacted to give the numerosity of a predicate. There are, however, logical mistakes in Peacocke's treatment of numbers, which undermine his intended analogy. Nevertheless Peacocke's account of possession conditions for concepts is not rendered inadequate simply by virtue of being deprived of the intended analogy an…Read more
  •  45
    Anti-realism and Logic. Truth as Eternal
    with W. D. Hart
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (4): 1485. 1989.
  •  50
    Proof and Paradox
    Dialectica 36 (2‐3): 265-296. 1982.
  •  40
    Contracting Intuitionistic Theories
    Studia Logica 80 (2-3): 369-391. 2005.
    I reformulate the AGM-account of contraction (which would yield an account also of revision). The reformulation involves using introduction and elimination rules for relational notions. Then I investigate the extent to which the two main methods of partial meet contraction and safe contraction can be employed for theories closed under intuitionistic consequence.
  •  37
    The relevance of premises to conclusions of core proofs
    Review of Symbolic Logic 8 (4): 743-784. 2015.
  •  9
    On and exist
    Analysis 40 (1): 5-7. 1980.
  • Book Reviews (review)
    Philosophia Mathematica 3 (2): 179-207. 1995.
  • Editor's Page: Editorial
    American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (4). 2006.
  •  72
    Normalizability, cut eliminability and paradox
    Synthese 199 (Suppl 3): 597-616. 2016.
    This is a reply to the considerations advanced by Schroeder-Heister and Tranchini as prima facie problematic for the proof-theoretic criterion of paradoxicality, as originally presented in Tennant and subsequently amended in Tennant. Countering these considerations lends new importance to the parallelized forms of elimination rules in natural deduction.
  •  1065
    Aristotle’s Syllogistic and Core Logic
    History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (2): 120-147. 2014.
    I use the Corcoran–Smiley interpretation of Aristotle's syllogistic as my starting point for an examination of the syllogistic from the vantage point of modern proof theory. I aim to show that fresh logical insights are afforded by a proof-theoretically more systematic account of all four figures. First I regiment the syllogisms in the Gentzen–Prawitz system of natural deduction, using the universal and existential quantifiers of standard first-order logic, and the usual formalizations of Aristo…Read more
  •  12
    The future with cloning
    In James H. Fetzer (ed.), Consciousness Evolving, John Benjamins. pp. 34--223. 2002.
  •  16
    Deflationism and the Godel Phenomena
    Mind 111 (443): 551-582. 2002.
    Any consistent and sufficiently strong system of first-order formal arithmetic fails to decide some independent Gödel sentence. We examine consistent first-order extensions of such systems. Our purpose is to discover what is minimally required by way of such extension in order to be able to prove the Gödel sentence in a non-trivial fashion. The extended methods of formal proof must capture the essentials of the so-called 'semantical argument' for the truth of the Gödel sentence. We are concerned…Read more
  •  87
    Anti-realist aporias
    Mind 109 (436): 825--854. 2000.
    Using a quantified propositional logic involving the operators it is known that and it is possible to know that, we formalize various interesting philosophical claims involved in the realism debate. We set out inferential rules for the epistemic modalities, ranging from ones that are obviously analytic, to ones that are epistemologically more substantive or even controversial. Then we investigate various aporias for the realism debate. These are constructively inconsistent triads of claims from …Read more
  •  26
    Revamping the restriction strategy
    In Joe Salerno (ed.), New Essays on the Knowability Paradox, Oxford University Press. 2009.
    This study continues the anti-realist’s quest for a principled way to avoid Fitch’s paradox. It is proposed that the Cartesian restriction on the anti-realist’s knowability principle ‘ϕ, therefore 3Kϕ’ should be formulated as a consistency requirement not on the premise ϕ of an application of the rule, but rather on the set of assumptions on which the relevant occurrence of ϕ depends. It is stressed, by reference to illustrative proofs, how important it is to have proofs in normal form before ap…Read more
  •  1
    Philosophy, Evolution & Human Nature
    with Florian von Schilcher
    Synthese 70 (3): 459-462. 1987.
  •  4
    Written for any readers interested in better harnessing philosophy's real value, this book covers a broad range of fundamental philosophical problems and certain intellectual techniques for addressing those problems. In Introducing Philosophy: God, Mind, World, and Logic, Neil Tennant helps any student in pursuit of a 'big picture' to think independently, question received dogma, and analyse problems incisively. It also connects philosophy to other areas of study at the university, enabling all …Read more
  •  46
    Game theory and conventiont
    Nordic Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1): 3-19. 2001.
    This paper rebuts criticisms by Hintikka of the author's account of game-theoretic semantics for classical logic. At issue are (i) the role of the axiom of choice in proving the equivalence of the game-theoretic account with the standard truth-theoretic account; (ii) the alleged need for quantification over strategies when providing a game-theoretic semantics; and (iii) the role of Tarski's Convention T. As a result of the ideas marshalled in response to Hintikka, the author puts forward a new c…Read more
  •  93
    Paradoxes of pure curiosity
    Theory and Decision 38 (3): 321-330. 1995.
    We consider how a rational decision theorist would justify committing resources to an investigation designed to satisfy pure curiosity. We derive a strange result about the need to be completely open-minded about the outcome
  •  27
    Victor vanquished
    Analysis 62 (2): 135-142. 2002.
  •  25
    On Maintaining Concentration
    Analysis 54 (3). 1994.
  •  106
    Cut for core logic
    Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (3): 450-479. 2012.
    The motivation for Core Logic is explained. Its system of proof is set out. It is then shown that, although the system has no Cut rule, its relation of deducibility obeys Cut with epistemic gain.
  •  98
    We present a logically detailed case-study of explanation and prediction in Newtonian mechanics. The case in question is that of a planet's elliptical orbit in the Sun's gravitational field. Care is taken to distinguish the respective contributions of the mathematics that is being applied, and of the empirical hypotheses that receive a mathematical formulation. This enables one to appreciate how in this case the overall logical structure of scientific explanation and prediction is exactly in acc…Read more
  •  33
    Formal games and forms for games
    Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (2). 1980.